Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • FIRST PART (FP: QQ 1-119)
      • Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] Out. Para. 1/1 - THE CAUSE OF EVIL (THREE ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] Out. Para. 1/1 - THE CAUSE OF EVIL (THREE ARTICLES)

We next inquire into the cause of evil. Concerning this there are three
points of inquire:

(1) Whether good can be the cause of evil?

(2) Whether the supreme good, God, is the cause of evil?

(3) Whether there be any supreme evil, which is the first cause of all
evils?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether good can be the cause of evil?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that good cannot be the cause of evil. For it is
said (Mt. 7:18): "A good tree cannot bring forth evil fruit."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, one contrary cannot be the cause of another. But evil is
the contrary to good. Therefore good cannot be the cause of evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, a deficient effect can proceed only from a deficient
cause. But evil is a deficient effect. Therefore its cause, if it has
one, is deficient. But everything deficient is an evil. Therefore the
cause of evil can only be evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that evil has no cause.
Therefore good is not the cause of evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (Contra Julian. i, 9): "There is no
possible source of evil except good."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, It must be said that every evil in some way has a cause.
For evil is the absence of the good, which is natural and due to a thing.
But that anything fail from its natural and due disposition can come only
from some cause drawing it out of its proper disposition. For a heavy
thing is not moved upwards except by some impelling force; nor does an
agent fail in its action except from some impediment. But only good can
be a cause; because nothing can be a cause except inasmuch as it is a
being, and every being, as such, is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Body Para. 2/3

And if we consider the special kinds of causes, we see that the agent,
the form, and the end, import some kind of perfection which belongs to
the notion of good. Even matter, as a potentiality to good, has the
nature of good. Now that good is the cause of evil by way of the material
cause was shown above (Q[48], A[3]). For it was shown that good is the
subject of evil. But evil has no formal cause, rather is it a privation
of form; likewise, neither has it a final cause, but rather is it a
privation of order to the proper end; since not only the end has the
nature of good, but also the useful, which is ordered to the end. Evil,
however, has a cause by way of an agent, not directly, but accidentally.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] Body Para. 3/3

In proof of this, we must know that evil is caused in the action
otherwise than in the effect. In the action evil is caused by reason of
the defect of some principle of action, either of the principal or the
instrumental agent; thus the defect in the movement of an animal may
happen by reason of the weakness of the motive power, as in the case of
children, or by reason only of the ineptitude of the instrument, as in
the lame. On the other hand, evil is caused in a thing, but not in the
proper effect of the agent, sometimes by the power of the agent,
sometimes by reason of a defect, either of the agent or of the matter. It is caused by reason of the power or perfection of the agent when there
necessarily follows on the form intended by the agent the privation of
another form; as, for instance, when on the form of fire there follows
the privation of the form of air or of water. Therefore, as the more
perfect the fire is in strength, so much the more perfectly does it
impress its own form, so also the more perfectly does it corrupt the
contrary. Hence that evil and corruption befall air and water comes from
the perfection of the fire: but this is accidental; because fire does not
aim at the privation of the form of water, but at the bringing in of its
own form, though by doing this it also accidentally causes the other. But
if there is a defect in the proper effect of the fire - as, for instance,
that it fails to heat - this comes either by defect of the action, which
implies the defect of some principle, as was said above, or by the
indisposition of the matter, which does not receive the action of the
fire, the agent. But this very fact that it is a deficient being is
accidental to good to which of itself it belongs to act. Hence it is true
that evil in no way has any but an accidental cause; and thus is good the
cause of evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: As Augustine says (Contra Julian. i): "The Lord calls an
evil will the evil tree, and a good will a good tree." Now, a good will
does not produce a morally bad act, since it is from the good will itself
that a moral act is judged to be good. Nevertheless the movement itself
of an evil will is caused by the rational creature, which is good; and
thus good is the cause of evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Good does not cause that evil which is contrary to itself,
but some other evil: thus the goodness of the fire causes evil to the
water, and man, good as to his nature, causes an act morally evil. And,
as explained above (Q[19], A[9]), this is by accident. Moreover, it does
happen sometimes that one contrary causes another by accident: for
instance, the exterior surrounding cold heats (the body) through the
concentration of the inward heat.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Evil has a deficient cause in voluntary things otherwise
than in natural things. For the natural agent produces the same kind of
effect as it is itself, unless it is impeded by some exterior thing; and
this amounts to some defect belonging to it. Hence evil never follows in
the effect, unless some other evil pre-exists in the agent or in the
matter, as was said above. But in voluntary things the defect of the
action comes from the will actually deficient, inasmuch as it does not
actually subject itself to its proper rule. This defect, however, is not
a fault, but fault follows upon it from the fact that the will acts with
this defect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Evil has no direct cause, but only an accidental cause, as
was said above.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the supreme good, God, is the cause of evil?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the supreme good, God, is the cause of evil.
For it is said (Is. 45:5,7): "I am the Lord, and there is no other God,
forming the light, and creating darkness, making peace, and creating
evil." And Amos 3:6, "Shall there be evil in a city, which the Lord hath
not done?"

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the effect of the secondary cause is reduced to the
first cause. But good is the cause of evil, as was said above (A[1]).
Therefore, since God is the cause of every good, as was shown above (Q[2]
, A[3]; Q[6], AA[1],4), it follows that also every evil is from God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, as is said by the Philosopher (Phys. ii, text 30), the
cause of both safety and danger of the ship is the same. But God is the
cause of the safety of all things. Therefore He is the cause of all
perdition and of all evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 21), that, "God is not the
author of evil because He is not the cause of tending to not-being."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As appears from what was said (A[1]), the evil which
consists in the defect of action is always caused by the defect of the
agent. But in God there is no defect, but the highest perfection, as was
shown above (Q[4], A[1]). Hence, the evil which consists in defect of
action, or which is caused by defect of the agent, is not reduced to God
as to its cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] Body Para. 2/2

But the evil which consists in the corruption of some things is reduced
to God as the cause. And this appears as regards both natural things and
voluntary things. For it was said (A[1]) that some agent inasmuch as it
produces by its power a form to which follows corruption and defect,
causes by its power that corruption and defect. But it is manifest that
the form which God chiefly intends in things created is the good of the
order of the universe. Now, the order of the universe requires, as was
said above (Q[22], A[2], ad 2; Q[48], A[2]), that there should be some
things that can, and do sometimes, fail. And thus God, by causing in
things the good of the order of the universe, consequently and as it were
by accident, causes the corruptions of things, according to 1 Kgs. 2:6:
"The Lord killeth and maketh alive." But when we read that "God hath not
made death" (Wis. 1:13), the sense is that God does not will death for
its own sake. Nevertheless the order of justice belongs to the order of
the universe; and this requires that penalty should be dealt out to
sinners. And so God is the author of the evil which is penalty, but not
of the evil which is fault, by reason of what is said above.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: These passages refer to the evil of penalty, and not to the
evil of fault.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The effect of the deficient secondary cause is reduced to
the first non-deficient cause as regards what it has of being and
perfection, but not as regards what it has of defect; just as whatever
there is of motion in the act of limping is caused by the motive power,
whereas what there is of obliqueness in it does not come from the motive
power, but from the curvature of the leg. And, likewise, whatever there
is of being and action in a bad action, is reduced to God as the cause;
whereas whatever defect is in it is not caused by God, but by the
deficient secondary cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The sinking of a ship is attributed to the sailor as the
cause, from the fact that he does not fulfil what the safety of the ship
requires; but God does not fail in doing what is necessary for the safety
of all. Hence there is no parity.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether there be one supreme evil which is the cause of every evil?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that there is one supreme evil which is the cause
of every evil. For contrary effects have contrary causes. But contrariety
is found in things, according to Ecclus. 33:15: "Good is set against
evil, and life against death; so also is the sinner against a just man."
Therefore there are many contrary principles, one of good, the other of
evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, if one contrary is in nature, so is the other. But the
supreme good is in nature, and is the cause of every good, as was shown
above (Q[2], A[3]; Q[6], AA[2],4). Therefore, also, there is a supreme
evil opposed to it as the cause of every evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, as we find good and better things, so we find evil and
worse. But good and better are so considered in relation to what is best.
Therefore evil and worse are so considered in relation to some supreme
evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, everything participated is reduced to what is essential.
But things which are evil among us are evil not essentially, but by
participation. Therefore we must seek for some supreme essential evil,
which is the cause of every evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, whatever is accidental is reduced to that which is "per
se." But good is the accidental cause of evil. Therefore, we must suppose
some supreme evil which is the "per se" cause of evils. Nor can it be
said that evil has no "per se" cause, but only an accidental cause; for
it would then follow that evil would not exist in the many, but only in
the few.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1

OBJ 6: Further, the evil of the effect is reduced to the evil of the
cause; because the deficient effect comes from the deficient cause, as
was said above (AA[1],2). But we cannot proceed to infinity in this
matter. Therefore, we must suppose one first evil as the cause of every
evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The supreme good is the cause of every being, as was
shown above (Q[2], A[3]; Q[6], A[4]). Therefore there cannot be any
principle opposed to it as the cause of evils.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 1/6

I answer that, It appears from what precedes that there is no one first
principle of evil, as there is one first principle of good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 2/6

First, indeed, because the first principle of good is essentially good,
as was shown above (Q[6], AA[3],4). But nothing can be essentially bad.
For it was shown above that every being, as such, is good (Q[5], A[3]);
and that evil can exist only in good as in its subject (Q[48], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 3/6

Secondly, because the first principle of good is the highest and perfect
good which pre-contains in itself all goodness, as shown above (Q[6],
A[2]). But there cannot be a supreme evil; because, as was shown above
(Q[48], A[4]), although evil always lessens good, yet it never wholly
consumes it; and thus, while good ever remains, nothing can be wholly and
perfectly bad. Therefore, the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 5) that "if
the wholly evil could be, it would destroy itself"; because all good
being destroyed (which it need be for something to be wholly evil), evil
itself would be taken away, since its subject is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 4/6

Thirdly, because the very nature of evil is against the idea of a first principle; both because every evil is caused by good, as was shown above
(A[1]), and because evil can be only an accidental cause, and thus it
cannot be the first cause, for the accidental cause is subsequent to the
direct cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 5/6

Those, however, who upheld two first principles, one good and the other
evil, fell into this error from the same cause, whence also arose other
strange notions of the ancients; namely, because they failed to consider
the universal cause of all being, and considered only the particular
causes of particular effects. For on that account, if they found a thing
hurtful to something by the power of its own nature, they thought that
the very nature of that thing was evil; as, for instance, if one should
say that the nature of fire was evil because it burnt the house of a poor
man. The judgment, however, of the goodness of anything does not depend
upon its order to any particular thing, but rather upon what it is in
itself, and on its order to the whole universe, wherein every part has
its own perfectly ordered place, as was said above (Q[47], A[2], ad 1).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 6/6

Likewise, because they found two contrary particular causes of two
contrary particular effects, they did not know how to reduce these
contrary particular causes to the universal common cause; and therefore
they extended the contrariety of causes even to the first principles. But
since all contraries agree in something common, it is necessary to search
for one common cause for them above their own contrary proper causes; as
above the contrary qualities of the elements exists the power of a
heavenly body; and above all things that exist, no matter how, there
exists one first principle of being, as was shown above (Q[2], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Contraries agree in one genus, and they also agree in the
nature of being; and therefore, although they have contrary particular
cause, nevertheless we must come at last to one first common cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Privation and habit belong naturally to the same subject.
Now the subject of privation is a being in potentiality, as was said
above (Q[48], A[3]). Hence, since evil is privation of good, as appears
from what was said above (Q[48], AA[1], 2,3), it is opposed to that good
which has some potentiality, but not to the supreme good, who is pure act.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Increase in intensity is in proportion to the nature of a
thing. And as the form is a perfection, so privation removes a
perfection. Hence every form, perfection, and good is intensified by
approach to the perfect term; but privation and evil by receding from
that term. Hence a thing is not said to be evil and worse, by reason of
access to the supreme evil, in the same way as it is said to be good and
better, by reason of access to the supreme good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: No being is called evil by participation, but by privation
of participation. Hence it is not necessary to reduce it to any essential
evil.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: Evil can only have an accidental cause, as was shown above
(A[1]). Hence reduction to any 'per se' cause of evil is impossible. And
to say that evil is in the greater number is simply false. For things
which are generated and corrupted, in which alone can there be natural
evil, are the smaller part of the whole universe. And again, in every
species the defect of nature is in the smaller number. In man alone does
evil appear as in the greater number; because the good of man as regards
the senses is not the good of man as man - that is, in regard to reason;
and more men seek good in regard to the senses than good according to
reason.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 6: In the causes of evil we do not proceed to infinity, but
reduce all evils to some good cause, whence evil follows accidentally.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License