Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT FS Prologue Para. 1/1 - FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (FS) (QQ[1]-114)
      • Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF USE, WHICH IS AN ACT OF THE WILL IN REGARD TO THE MEANS (FOUR ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF USE, WHICH IS AN ACT OF THE WILL IN REGARD TO THE MEANS (FOUR ARTICLES)

We must now consider use; concerning which there are four points of
inquiry:

(1) Whether use is an act of the will?

(2) Whether it is to be found in irrational animals?

(3) Whether it regards the means only, or the end also?

(4) Of the relation of use to choice.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether use is an act of the will?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that use is not an act of the will. For Augustine
says (De Doctr. Christ. i, 4) that "to use is to refer that which is the
object of use to the obtaining of something else." But "to refer"
something to another is an act of the reason to which it belongs to
compare and to direct. Therefore use is an act of the reason and not of
the will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 22) that man "goes
forward to the operation, and this is called impulse; then he makes use
(of the powers) and this is called use." But operation belongs to the
executive power; and the act of the will does not follow the act of the
executive power, on the contrary execution comes last. Therefore use is
not an act of the will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 30): "All things that were
made were made for man's use, because reason with which man is endowed
uses all things by its judgment of them." But judgment of things created
by God belongs to the speculative reason; which seems to be altogether
distinct from the will, which is the principle of human acts. Therefore
use is not an act of the will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. x, 11): "To use is to apply to
something to purpose of the will."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, The use of a thing implies the application of that thing
to an operation: hence the operation to which we apply a thing is called
its use; thus the use of a horse is to ride, and the use of a stick is to
strike. Now we apply to an operation not only the interior principles of
action, viz. the powers of the soul or the members of the body; as the
intellect, to understand; and the eye, to see; but also external things,
as a stick, to strike. But it is evident that we do not apply external
things to an operation save through the interior principles which are
either the powers of the soul, or the habits of those powers, or the
organs which are parts of the body. Now it has been shown above (Q[9],
A[1]) that it is the will which moves the soul's powers to their acts,
and this is to apply them to operation. Hence it is evident that first
and principally use belongs to the will as first mover; to the reason, as
directing; and to the other powers as executing the operation, which
powers are compared to the will which applies them to act, as the
instruments are compared to the principal agent. Now action is properly
ascribed, not to the instrument, but to the principal agent, as building
is ascribed to the builder, not to his tools. Hence it is evident that
use is, properly speaking, an act of the will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Reason does indeed refer one thing to another; but the will
tends to that which is referred by the reason to something else. And in
this sense to use is to refer one thing to another.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Damascene is speaking of use in so far as it belongs to the
executive powers.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Even the speculative reason is applied by the will to the
act of understanding or judging. Consequently the speculative reason is
said to use, in so far as it is moved by the will, in the same way as the
other powers.

(tm)Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether use is to be found in irrational animals?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that use is to be found in irrational animals. For
it is better to enjoy than to use, because, as Augustine says (De Trin.
x, 10): "We use things by referring them to something else which we are
to enjoy." But enjoyment is to be found in irrational animals, as stated
above (Q[11], A[2]). Much more, therefore, is it possible for them to use.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, to apply the members to action is to use them. But
irrational animals apply their members to action; for instance, their
feet, to walk; their horns, to strike. Therefore it is possible for
irrational animals to use.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 30): "None but a rational
animal can make use of a thing."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, as stated above (A[1]), to use is to apply an active
principle to action: thus to consent is to apply the appetitive movement
to the desire of something, as stated above (Q[15], AA[1],2,3). Now he
alone who has the disposal of a thing, can apply it to something else;
and this belongs to him alone who knows how to refer it to something
else, which is an act of the reason. And therefore none but a rational
animal consents and uses.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: To enjoy implies the absolute movement of the appetite to
the appetible: whereas to use implies a movement of the appetite to
something as directed to something else. If therefore we compare use and
enjoyment in respect of their objects, enjoyment is better than use;
because that which is appetible absolutely is better than that which is
appetible only as directed to something else. But if we compare them in
respect of the apprehensive power that precedes them, greater excellence
is required on the part of use: because to direct one thing to another is
an act of reason; whereas to apprehend something absolutely is within the
competency even of sense.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Animals by means of their members do something from natural
instinct; not through knowing the relation of their members to these
operations. Wherefore, properly speaking, they do not apply their members
to action, nor do they use them.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether use regards also the last end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that use can regard also the last end. For
Augustine says (De Trin. x, 11): "Whoever enjoys, uses." But man enjoys
the last end. Therefore he uses the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, "to use is to apply something to the purpose of the
will" (De Trin. x, 11). But the last end, more than anything else, is the
object of the will's application. Therefore it can be the object of use.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, Hilary says (De Trin. ii) that "Eternity is in the
Father, Likeness in the Image," i.e. in the Son, "Use in the Gift," i.e.
in the Holy Ghost. But the Holy Ghost, since He is God, is the last end.
Therefore the last end can be the object of use.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 30): "No one rightly uses
God, but one enjoys Him." But God alone is the last end. Therefore we
cannot use the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Use, as stated above (A[1]), implies the application of
one thing to another. Now that which is applied to another is regarded in
the light of means to an end; and consequently use always regards the
means. For this reason things that are adapted to a certain end are said
to be "useful"; in fact their very usefulness is sometimes called use.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

It must, however, be observed that the last end may be taken in two
ways: first, simply; secondly, in respect of an individual. For since the
end, as stated above (Q[1], A[8]; Q[2], A[7]), signifies sometimes the
thing itself, and sometimes the attainment or possession of that thing
(thus the miser's end is either money or the possession of it); it is
evident that, simply speaking, the last end is the thing itself; for the
possession of money is good only inasmuch as there is some good in money.
But in regard to the individual, the obtaining of money is the last end;
for the miser would not seek for money, save that he might have it.
Therefore, simply and properly speaking, a man enjoys money, because he
places his last end therein; but in so far as he seeks to possess it, he
is said to use it.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Augustine is speaking of use in general, in so far as it
implies the relation of an end to the enjoyment which a man seeks in that
end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The end is applied to the purpose of the will, that the
will may find rest in it. Consequently this rest in the end, which is the
enjoyment thereof, is in this sense called use of the end. But the means
are applied to the will's purpose, not only in being used as means, but
as ordained to something else in which the will finds rest.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The words of Hilary refer to use as applicable to rest in
the last end; just as, speaking in a general sense, one may be said to
use the end for the purpose of attaining it, as stated above. Hence
Augustine says (De Trin. vi, 10) that "this love, delight, felicity, or
happiness, is called use by him."


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether use precedes choice?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that use precedes choice. For nothing follows after
choice, except execution. But use, since it belongs to the will, precedes
execution. Therefore it precedes choice also.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the absolute precedes the relative. Therefore the less
relative precedes the more relative. But choice implies two relations:
one, of the thing chosen, in relation to the end; the other, of the thing
chosen, in respect of that to which it is preferred; whereas use implies
relation to the end only. Therefore use precedes choice.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the will uses the other powers in so far as it removes
them. But the will moves itself, too, as stated above (Q[9], A[3]).
Therefore it uses itself, by applying itself to act. But it does this
when it consents. Therefore there is use in consent. But consent precedes
choice as stated above (Q[15], A[3], ad 3). Therefore use does also.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 22) that "the will
after choosing has an impulse to the operation, and afterwards it uses
(the powers)." Therefore use follows choice.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, The will has a twofold relation to the thing willed. One,
according as the thing willed is, in a way, in the willing subject, by a
kind of proportion or order to the thing willed. Wherefore those things
that are naturally proportionate to a certain end, are said to desire
that end naturally. Yet to have an end thus is to have it imperfectly.
Now every imperfect thing tends to perfection. And therefore both the
natural and the voluntary appetite tend to have the end in reality; and
this is to have it perfectly. This is the second relation of the will to
the thing willed.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

Now the thing willed is not only the end, but also the means. And the
last act that belongs to the first relation of the will to the means, is
choice; for there the will becomes fully proportionate, by willing the
means fully. Use, on the other hand, belongs to the second relation of
the will, in respect of which it tends to the realization of the thing
willed. Wherefore it is evident that use follows choice; provided that by
use we mean the will's use of the executive power in moving it. But since
the will, in a way, moves the reason also, and uses it, we may take the
use of the means, as consisting in the consideration of the reason,
whereby it refers the means to the end. In this sense use precedes choice.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The motion of the will to the execution of the work,
precedes execution, but follows choice. And so, since use belongs to that
very motion of the will, it stands between choice and execution.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: What is essentially relative is after the absolute; but the
thing to which relation is referred need not come after. Indeed, the more
a cause precedes, the more numerous the effects to which it has relation.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[16] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Choice precedes use, if they be referred to the same
object. But nothing hinders the use of one thing preceding the choice of
another. And since the acts of the will react on one another, in each act
of the will we can find both consent and choice and use; so that we may
say that the will consents to choose, and consents to consent, and uses
itself in consenting and choosing. And such acts as are ordained to that
which precedes, precede also.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License