Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT FS Prologue Para. 1/1 - FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (FS) (QQ[1]-114)
      • Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF CONCUPISCENCE (FOUR ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF CONCUPISCENCE (FOUR ARTICLES)

We have now to consider concupiscence: under which head there are four
points of inquiry:

(1) Whether concupiscence is in the sensitive appetite only?

(2) Whether concupiscence is a specific passion?

(3) Whether some concupiscences are natural, and some not natural?

(4) Whether concupiscence is infinite?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether concupiscence is in the sensitive appetite only?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that concupiscence is not only in the sensitive
appetite. For there is a concupiscence of wisdom, according to Wis. 6:21:
"The concupiscence [Douay: 'desire'] of wisdom bringeth to the
everlasting kingdom." But the sensitive appetite can have no tendency to
wisdom. Therefore concupiscence is not only in the sensitive appetite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the desire for the commandments of God is not in the
sensitive appetite: in fact the Apostle says (Rm. 7:18): "There dwelleth
not in me, that is to say, in my flesh, that which is good." But desire
for God's commandments is an act of concupiscence, according to Ps.
118:20: "My soul hath coveted [concupivit] to long for thy
justifications." Therefore concupiscence is not only in the sensitive
appetite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, to each power, its proper good is a matter of
concupiscence. Therefore concupiscence is in each power of the soul, and
not only in the sensitive appetite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 12) that "the
irrational part which is subject and amenable to reason, is divided into
the faculties of concupiscence and anger. This is the irrational part of
the soul, passive and appetitive." Therefore concupiscence is in the
sensitive appetite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As the Philosopher says (Rhet. i, 11), "concupiscence is
a craving for that which is pleasant." Now pleasure is twofold, as we
shall state later on (Q[31], AA[3],4): one is in the intelligible good,
which is the good of reason; the other is in good perceptible to the
senses. The former pleasure seems to belong to soul alone: whereas the
latter belongs to both soul and body: because the sense is a power seated
in a bodily organ: wherefore sensible good is the good of the whole
composite. Now concupiscence seems to be the craving for this latter
pleasure, since it belongs to the united soul and body, as is implied by
the Latin word "concupiscentia." Therefore, properly speaking,
concupiscence is in the sensitive appetite, and in the concupiscible
faculty, which takes its name from it.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The craving for wisdom, or other spiritual goods, is
sometimes called concupiscence; either by reason of a certain likeness;
or on account of the craving in the higher part of the soul being so
vehement that it overflows into the lower appetite, so that the latter
also, in its own way, tends to the spiritual good, following the lead of
the higher appetite, the result being that the body itself renders its
service in spiritual matters, according to Ps. 83:3: "My heart and my
flesh have rejoiced in the living God."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Properly speaking, desire may be not only in the lower, but
also in the higher appetite. For it does not imply fellowship in craving,
as concupiscence does; but simply movement towards the thing desired.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: It belongs to each power of the soul to seek its proper
good by the natural appetite, which does not arise from apprehension. But
the craving for good, by the animal appetite, which arises from
apprehension, belongs to the appetitive power alone. And to crave a thing
under the aspect of something delightful to the senses, wherein
concupiscence properly consists, belongs to the concupiscible power.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether concupiscence is a specific passion?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that concupiscence is not a specific passion of the
concupiscible power. For passions are distinguished by their objects. But
the object of the concupiscible power is something delightful to the
senses; and this is also the object of concupiscence, as the Philosopher
declares (Rhet. i, 11). Therefore concupiscence is not a specific passion
of the concupiscible faculty.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 33) that "covetousness is
the love of transitory things": so that it is not distinct from love. But
all specific passions are distinct from one another. Therefore
concupiscence is not a specific passion in the concupiscible faculty.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, to each passion of the concupiscible faculty there is a
specific contrary passion in that faculty, as stated above (Q[23], A[4]).
But no specific passion of the concupiscible faculty is contrary to
concupiscence. For Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 12) that "good when
desired gives rise to concupiscence; when present, it gives joy: in like
manner, the evil we apprehend makes us fear, the evil that is present
makes us sad": from which we gather that as sadness is contrary to joy,
so is fear contrary to concupiscence. But fear is not in the
concupiscible, but in the irascible part. Therefore concupiscence is not
a specific passion of the concupiscible faculty.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Concupiscence is caused by love, and tends to pleasure,
both of which are passions of the concupiscible faculty. Hence it is
distinguished from the other concupiscible passions, as a specific
passion.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (A[1]; Q[23], A[1]), the good which gives
pleasure to the senses is the common object of the concupiscible faculty.
Hence the various concupiscible passions are distinguished according to
the differences of that good. Now the diversity of this object can arise
from the very nature of the object, or from a diversity in its active
power. The diversity, derived from the nature of the active object,
causes a material difference of passions: while the difference in regard
to its active power causes a formal diversity of passions, in respect of
which the passions differ specifically.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] Body Para. 2/2

Now the nature of the motive power of the end or of the good, differs
according as it is really present, or absent: because, according as it is
present, it causes the faculty to find rest in it; whereas, according as
it is absent, it causes the faculty to be moved towards it. Wherefore the
object of sensible pleasure causes love, inasmuch as, so to speak, it
attunes and conforms the appetite to itself; it causes concupiscence,
inasmuch as, when absent, it draws the faculty to itself; and it causes
pleasure, inasmuch as, when present, it makes the faculty to find rest in
itself. Accordingly, concupiscence is a passion differing "in species"
from both love and pleasure. But concupiscences of this or that
pleasurable object differ "in number."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Pleasurable good is the object of concupiscence, not
absolutely, but considered as absent: just as the sensible, considered as
past, is the object of memory. For these particular conditions diversify
the species of passions, and even of the powers of the sensitive part,
which regards particular things.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: In the passage quoted we have causal, not essential
predication: for covetousness is not essentially love, but an effect of
love. We may also say that Augustine is taking covetousness in a wide
sense, for any movement of the appetite in respect of good to come: so
that it includes both love and hope.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The passion which is directly contrary to concupiscence has
no name, and stands in relation to evil, as concupiscence in regard to
good. But since, like fear, it regards the absent evil; sometimes it goes
by the name of fear, just as hope is sometimes called covetousness. For a
small good or evil is reckoned as though it were nothing: and
consequently every movement of the appetite in future good or evil is
called hope or fear, which regard good and evil as arduous.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether some concupiscences are natural, and some not natural?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that concupiscences are not divided into those
which are natural and those which are not. For concupiscence belongs to
the animal appetite, as stated above (A[1], ad 3). But the natural
appetite is contrasted with the animal appetite. Therefore no
concupiscence is natural.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, material differences makes no difference of species, but
only numerical difference; a difference which is outside the purview of
science. But if some concupiscences are natural, and some not, they
differ only in respect of their objects; which amounts to a material
difference, which is one of number only. Therefore concupiscences should
not be divided into those that are natural and those that are not.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, reason is contrasted with nature, as stated in Phys. ii,
5. If therefore in man there is a concupiscence which is not natural, it
must needs be rational. But this is impossible: because, since
concupiscence is a passion, it belongs to the sensitive appetite, and not
to the will, which is the rational appetite. Therefore there are no
concupiscences which are not natural.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 11 and Rhetor. i, 11)
distinguishes natural concupiscences from those that are not natural.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (A[1]), concupiscence is the craving for
pleasurable good. Now a thing is pleasurable in two ways. First, because
it is suitable to the nature of the animal; for example, food, drink, and
the like: and concupiscence of such pleasurable things is said to be
natural. Secondly, a thing is pleasurable because it is apprehended as
suitable to the animal: as when one apprehends something as good and
suitable, and consequently takes pleasure in it: and concupiscence of
such pleasurable things is said to be not natural, and is more wont to be
called "cupidity."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

Accordingly concupiscences of the first kind, or natural
concupiscences, are common to men and other animals: because to both is
there something suitable and pleasurable according to nature: and in
these all men agree; wherefore the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 11) calls
them "common" and "necessary." But concupiscences of the second kind are
proper to men, to whom it is proper to devise something as good and
suitable, beyond that which nature requires. Hence the Philosopher says
(Rhet. i, 11) that the former concupiscences are "irrational," but the
latter, "rational." And because different men reason differently,
therefore the latter are also called (Ethic. iii, 11) "peculiar and
acquired," i.e. in addition to those that are natural.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The same thing that is the object of the natural appetite,
may be the object of the animal appetite, once it is apprehended. And in
this way there may be an animal concupiscence of food, drink, and the
like, which are objects of the natural appetite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The difference between those concupiscences that are
natural and those that are not, is not merely a material difference; it
is also, in a way, formal, in so far as it arises from a difference in
the active object. Now the object of the appetite is the apprehended
good. Hence diversity of the active object follows from diversity of
apprehension: according as a thing is apprehended as suitable, either by
absolute apprehension, whence arise natural concupiscences, which the
Philosopher calls "irrational" (Rhet. i, 11); or by apprehension together
with deliberation, whence arise those concupiscences that are not
natural, and which for this very reason the Philosopher calls "rational"
(Rhet. i, 11).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Man has not only universal reason, pertaining to the
intellectual faculty; but also particular reason pertaining to the
sensitive faculty, as stated in the FP, Q[78], A[4]; FP, Q[81], A[3]: so
that even rational concupiscence may pertain to the sensitive appetite.
Moreover the sensitive appetite can be moved by the universal reason
also, through the medium of the particular imagination.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether concupiscence is infinite?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that concupiscence is not infinite. For the object
of concupiscence is good, which has the aspect of an end. But where there
is infinity there is no end (Metaph. ii, 2). Therefore concupiscence
cannot be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, concupiscence is of the fitting good, since it proceeds
from love. But the infinite is without proportion, and therefore
unfitting. Therefore concupiscence cannot be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, there is no passing through infinite things: and thus
there is no reaching an ultimate term in them. But the subject of
concupiscence is not delighted until he attain the ultimate term.
Therefore, if concupiscence were infinite, no delight would ever ensue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3) that "since
concupiscence is infinite, men desire an infinite number of things."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, As stated above (A[3]), concupiscence is twofold; one is
natural, the other is not natural. Natural concupiscence cannot be
actually infinite: because it is of that which nature requires; and
nature ever tends to something finite and fixed. Hence man never desires
infinite meat, or infinite drink. But just as in nature there is
potential successive infinity, so can this kind of concupiscence be
infinite successively; so that, for instance, after getting food, a man
may desire food yet again; and so of anything else that nature requires:
because these bodily goods, when obtained, do not last for ever, but
fail. Hence Our Lord said to the woman of Samaria (Jn. 4:13): "Whosever
drinketh of this water, shall thirst again."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Body Para. 2/3

But non-natural concupiscence is altogether infinite. Because, as stated
above (A[3]), it follows from the reason, and it belongs to the reason to
proceed to infinity. Hence he that desires riches, may desire to be rich,
not up to a certain limit, but to be simply as rich as possible.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] Body Para. 3/3

Another reason may be assigned, according to the Philosopher (Polit. i,
3), why a certain concupiscence is finite, and another infinite. Because
concupiscence of the end is always infinite: since the end is desired for
its own sake, e.g. health: and thus greater health is more desired, and
so on to infinity; just as, if a white thing of itself dilates the sight,
that which is more white dilates yet more. On the other hand,
concupiscence of the means is not infinite, because the concupiscence of
the means is in suitable proportion to the end. Consequently those who
place their end in riches have an infinite concupiscence of riches;
whereas those who desire riches, on account of the necessities of life,
desire a finite measure of riches, sufficient for the necessities of
life, as the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3). The same applies to the
concupiscence of any other things.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Every object of concupiscence is taken as something finite:
either because it is finite in reality, as being once actually desired;
or because it is finite as apprehended. For it cannot be apprehended as
infinite, since the infinite is that "from which, however much we may
take, there always remains something to be taken" (Phys. iii, 6).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The reason is possessed of infinite power, in a certain
sense, in so far as it can consider a thing infinitely, as appears in the
addition of numbers and lines. Consequently, the infinite, taken in a
certain way, is proportionate to reason. In fact the universal which the
reason apprehends, is infinite in a sense, inasmuch as it contains
potentially an infinite number of singulars.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[30] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: In order that a man be delighted, there is no need for him
to realize all that he desires: for he delights in the realization of
each object of his concupiscence.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License