Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT FS Prologue Para. 1/1 - FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (FS) (QQ[1]-114)
      • Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF THE SUBJECT OF VIRTUE (SIX ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF THE SUBJECT OF VIRTUE (SIX ARTICLES)

We now have to consider the subject of virtue, about which there are six
points of inquiry:

(1) Whether the subject of virtue is a power of the soul?

(2) Whether one virtue can be in several powers?

(3) Whether the intellect can be the subject of virtue?
(4) Whether the irascible and concupiscible faculties can be the subject
of virtue?

(5) Whether the sensitive powers of apprehension can be the subject of
virtue?

(6) Whether the will can be the subject of virtue?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the subject of virtue is a power of the soul?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the subject of virtue is not a power of the
soul. For Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. ii, 19) that "virtue is that by
which we live righteously." But we live by the essence of the soul, and
not by a power of the soul. Therefore virtue is not a power, but in the
essence of the soul.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 6) that "virtue is that
which makes its possessor good, and his work good likewise." But as work
is set up by power, so he that has a virtue is set up by the essence of
the soul. Therefore virtue does not belong to the power, any more than to
the essence of the soul.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, power is in the second species of quality. But virtue is
a quality, as we have said above (Q[55], A[4]): and quality is not the
subject of quality. Therefore a power of the soul is not the subject of
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, "Virtue is the limit of power" (De Coelo ii). But the
limit is in that of which it is the limit. Therefore virtue is in a power
of the soul.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, It can be proved in three ways that virtue belongs to a
power of the soul. First, from the notion of the very essence of virtue,
which implies perfection of a power; for perfection is in that which it
perfects. Secondly, from the fact that virtue is an operative habit, as
we have said above (Q[55], A[2]): for all operation proceeds from the
soul through a power. Thirdly, from the fact that virtue disposes to that
which is best: for the best is the end, which is either a thing's
operation, or something acquired by an operation proceeding from the
thing's power. Therefore a power of the soul is the subject of virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: "To live" may be taken in two ways. Sometimes it is taken
for the very existence of the living thing: in this way it belongs to the
essence of the soul, which is the principle of existence in the living
thing. But sometimes "to live" is taken for the operation of the living
thing: in this sense, by virtue we live righteously, inasmuch as by
virtue we perform righteous actions.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Good is either the end, or something referred to the end.
And therefore, since the good of the worker consists in the work, this
fact also, that virtue makes the worker good, is referred to the work,
and consequently, to the power.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: One accident is said to be the subject of another, not as
though one accident could uphold another; but because one accident
inheres to substance by means of another, as color to the body by means
of the surface; so that surface is said to be the subject of color. In
this way a power of the soul is said to be the subject of virtue.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether one virtue can be in several powers?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that one virtue can be in several powers. For
habits are known by their acts. But one act proceeds in various way from
several powers: thus walking proceeds from the reason as directing, from
the will as moving, and from the motive power as executing. Therefore
also one habit can be in several powers.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 4) that three things
are required for virtue, namely: "to know, to will, and to work
steadfastly." But "to know" belongs to the intellect, and "to will"
belongs to the will. Therefore virtue can be in several powers.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, prudence is in the reason since it is "the right reason
of things to be done" (Ethic. vi, 5). And it is also in the will: for it
cannot exist together with a perverse will (Ethic. vi, 12). Therefore one
virtue can be in two powers.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The subject of virtue is a power of the soul. But the
same accident cannot be in several subjects. Therefore one virtue cannot
be in several powers of the soul.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, It happens in two ways that one thing is subjected in
two. First, so that it is in both on an equal footing. In this way it is
impossible for one virtue to be in two powers: since diversity of powers
follows the generic conditions of the objects, while diversity of habits
follows the specific conditions thereof: and so wherever there is
diversity of powers, there is diversity of habits; but not vice versa. In
another way one thing can be subjected in two or more, not on an equal
footing, but in a certain order. And thus one virtue can belong to
several powers, so that it is in one chiefly, while it extends to others
by a kind of diffusion, or by way of a disposition, in so far as one
power is moved by another, and one power receives from another.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: One act cannot belong to several powers equally, and in the
same degree; but only from different points of view, and in various
degrees.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: "To know" is a condition required for moral virtue,
inasmuch as moral virtue works according to right reason. But moral
virtue is essentially in the appetite.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Prudence is really subjected in reason: but it presupposes
as its principle the rectitude of the will, as we shall see further on
(A[3]; Q[57], A[4]).


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the intellect can be the subject of virtue?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the intellect is not the subject of virtue.
For Augustine says (De Moribus Eccl. xv) that all virtue is love. But the
subject of love is not the intellect, but the appetitive power alone.
Therefore no virtue is in the intellect.
Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, virtue is referred to good, as is clear from what has
been said above (Q[55], A[3]). Now good is not the object of the
intellect, but of the appetitive power. Therefore the subject of virtue
is not the intellect, but the appetitive power.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, virtue is that "which makes its possessor good," as the
Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 6). But the habit which perfects the
intellect does not make its possessor good: since a man is not said to be
a good man on account of his science or his art. Therefore the intellect
is not the subject of virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The mind is chiefly called the intellect. But the
subject of virtue is the mind, as is clear from the definition, above
given, of virtue (Q[55], A[4]). Therefore the intellect is the subject of
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Body Para. 1/4

I answer that, As we have said above (Q[55], A[3]), a virtue is a habit
by which we work well. Now a habit may be directed to a good act in two
ways. First, in so far as by the habit a man acquires an aptness to a
good act; for instance, by the habit of grammar man has the aptness to
speak correctly. But grammar does not make a man always speak correctly:
for a grammarian may be guilty of a barbarism or make a solecism: and the
case is the same with other sciences and arts. Secondly, a habit may
confer not only aptness to act, but also the right use of that aptness:
for instance, justice not only gives man the prompt will to do just
actions, but also makes him act justly.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Body Para. 2/4

And since good, and, in like manner, being, is said of a thing simply,
in respect, not of what it is potentially, but of what it is actually:
therefore from having habits of the latter sort, man is said simply to do
good, and to be good; for instance, because he is just, or temperate; and
in like manner as regards other such virtues. And since virtue is that
"which makes its possessor good, and his work good likewise," these
latter habits are called virtuous simply: because they make the work to
be actually good, and the subject good simply. But the first kind of
habits are not called virtues simply: because they do not make the work
good except in regard to a certain aptness, nor do they make their
possessor good simply. For through being gifted in science or art, a man
is said to be good, not simply, but relatively; for instance, a good
grammarian or a good smith. And for this reason science and art are often
divided against virtue; while at other times they are called virtues
(Ethic. vi, 2).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Body Para. 3/4

Hence the subject of a habit which is called a virtue in a relative
sense, can be the intellect, and not only the practical intellect, but
also the speculative, without any reference to the will: for thus the
Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 3) holds that science, wisdom and understanding,
and also art, are intellectual virtues. But the subject of a habit which
is called a virtue simply, can only be the will, or some power in so far
as it is moved by the will. And the reason of this is, that the will
moves to their acts all those other powers that are in some way rational,
as we have said above (Q[9], A[1]; Q[17], AA[1],5; FP, Q[82], A[4]): and
therefore if man do well actually, this is because he has a good will.
Therefore the virtue which makes a man to do well actually, and not
merely to have the aptness to do well, must be either in the will
itself; or in some power as moved by the will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] Body Para. 4/4

Now it happens that the intellect is moved by the will, just as are the
other powers: for a man considers something actually, because he wills to
do so. And therefore the intellect, in so far as it is subordinate to the
will, can be the subject of virtue absolutely so called. And in this way
the speculative intellect, or the reason, is the subject of Faith: for
the intellect is moved by the command of the will to assent to what is of
faith: for "no man believeth, unless he will" [*Augustine: Tract. xxvi in
Joan.]. But the practical intellect is the subject of prudence. For since
prudence is the right reason of things to be done, it is a condition
thereof that man be rightly disposed in regard to the principles of this
reason of things to be done, that is in regard to their ends, to which
man is rightly disposed by the rectitude of the will, just as to the
principles of speculative truth he is rightly disposed by the natural
light of the active intellect. And therefore as the subject of science,
which is the right reason of speculative truths, is the speculative
intellect in its relation to the active intellect, so the subject of
prudence is the practical intellect in its relation to the right will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The saying of Augustine is to be understood of virtue
simply so called: not that every virtue is love simply: but that it
depends in some way on love, in so far as it depends on the will, whose
first movement consists in love, as we have said above (Q[25], AA[1],2,3;
Q[27], A[4]; FP, Q[20], A[1]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The good of each thing is its end: and therefore, as truth
is the end of the intellect, so to know truth is the good act of the
intellect. Whence the habit, which perfects the intellect in regard to
the knowledge of truth, whether speculative or practical, is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: This objection considers virtue simply so called.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the irascible and concupiscible powers are the subject of virtue?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the irascible and concupiscible powers cannot
be the subject of virtue. For these powers are common to us and dumb
animals. But we are now speaking of virtue as proper to man, since for
this reason it is called human virtue. It is therefore impossible for
human virtue to be in the irascible and concupiscible powers which are
parts of the sensitive appetite, as we have said in the FP, Q[81], A[2].

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the sensitive appetite is a power which makes use of a
corporeal organ. But the good of virtue cannot be in man's body: for the
Apostle says (Rm. 7): "I know that good does not dwell in my flesh."
Therefore the sensitive appetite cannot be the subject of virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, Augustine proves (De Moribus Eccl. v) that virtue is not
in the body but in the soul, for the reason that the body is ruled by the
soul: wherefore it is entirely due to his soul that a man make good use
of his body: "For instance, if my coachman, through obedience to my
orders, guides well the horses which he is driving; this is all due to
me." But just as the soul rules the body, so also does the reason rule
the sensitive appetite. Therefore that the irascible and concupiscible
powers are rightly ruled, is entirely due to the rational powers. Now
"virtue is that by which we live rightly," as we have said above (Q[55],
A[4]). Therefore virtue is not in the irascible and concupiscible powers,
but only in the rational powers.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, "the principal act of moral virtue is choice" (Ethic.
viii, 13). Now choice is not an act of the irascible and concupiscible
powers, but of the rational power, as we have said above (Q[13], A[2]).
Therefore moral virtue is not in the irascible and concupiscible powers,
but in the reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Fortitude is assigned to the irascible power, and
temperance to the concupiscible power. Whence the Philosopher (Ethic.
iii, 10) says that "these virtues belong to the irrational part of the
soul."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, The irascible and concupiscible powers can be considered
in two ways. First, in themselves, in so far as they are parts of the
sensitive appetite: and in this way they are not competent to be the
subject of virtue. Secondly, they can be considered as participating in
the reason, from the fact that they have a natural aptitude to obey
reason. And thus the irascible or concupiscible power can be the subject
of human virtue: for, in so far as it participates in the reason, it is
the principle of a human act. And to these powers we must needs assign
virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] Body Para. 2/2
For it is clear that there are some virtues in the irascible and
concupiscible powers. Because an act, which proceeds from one power
according as it is moved by another power, cannot be perfect, unless both
powers be well disposed to the act: for instance, the act of a craftsman
cannot be successful unless both the craftsman and his instrument be well
disposed to act. Therefore in the matter of the operations of the
irascible and concupiscible powers, according as they are moved by
reason, there must needs be some habit perfecting in respect of acting
well, not only the reason, but also the irascible and concupiscible
powers. And since the good disposition of the power which moves through
being moved, depends on its conformity with the power that moves it:
therefore the virtue which is in the irascible and concupiscible powers
is nothing else but a certain habitual conformity of these powers to
reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The irascible and concupiscible powers considered in
themselves, as parts of the sensitive appetite, are common to us and dumb
animals. But in so far as they are rational by participation, and are
obedient to the reason, they are proper to man. And in this way they can
be the subject of human virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Just as human flesh has not of itself the good of virtue,
but is made the instrument of a virtuous act, inasmuch as being moved by
reason, we "yield our members to serve justice"; so also, the irascible
and concupiscible powers, of themselves indeed, have not the good of
virtue, but rather the infection of the "fomes": whereas, inasmuch as
they are in conformity with reason, the good of reason is begotten in
them.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The body is ruled by the soul, and the irascible and
concupiscible powers by the reason, but in different ways. For the body
obeys the soul blindly without any contradiction, in those things in
which it has a natural aptitude to be moved by the soul: whence the
Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3) that the "soul rules the body with a
despotic command" as the master rules his slave: wherefore the entire
movement of the body is referred to the soul. For this reason virtue is
not in the body, but in the soul. But the irascible and concupiscible
powers do not obey the reason blindly; on the contrary, they have their
own proper movements, by which, at times, they go against reason, whence
the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3) that the "reason rules the irascible
and concupiscible powers by a political command" such as that by which
free men are ruled, who have in some respects a will of their own. And
for this reason also must there be some virtues in the irascible and
concupiscible powers, by which these powers are well disposed to act.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: In choice there are two things, namely, the intention of
the end, and this belongs to the moral virtue; and the preferential
choice of that which is unto the end, and this belongs to prudence
(Ethic. vi, 2,5). But that the irascible and concupiscible powers have a
right intention of the end in regard to the passions of the soul, is due
to the good disposition of these powers. And therefore those moral
virtues which are concerned with the passions are in the irascible and
concupiscible powers, but prudence is in the reason.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the sensitive powers of apprehension are the subject of virtue?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that it is possible for virtue to be in the
interior sensitive powers of apprehension. For the sensitive appetite can
be the subject of virtue, in so far as it obeys reason. But the interior
sensitive powers of apprehension obey reason: for the powers of
imagination, of cogitation, and of memory [*Cf. FP, Q[78], A[4]] act at
the command of reason. Therefore in these powers there can be virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, as the rational appetite, which is the will, can be
hindered or helped in its act, by the sensitive appetite, so also can the
intellect or reason be hindered or helped by the powers mentioned above.
As, therefore, there can be virtue in the interior powers of appetite,
so also can there be virtue in the interior powers of apprehension.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, prudence is a virtue, of which Cicero (De Invent.
Rhetor. ii) says that memory is a part. Therefore also in the power of
memory there can be a virtue: and in like manner, in the other interior
sensitive powers of apprehension.
Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, All virtues are either intellectual or moral (Ethic.
ii, 1). Now all the moral virtues are in the appetite; while the
intellectual virtues are in the intellect or reason, as is clear from
Ethic. vi, 1. Therefore there is no virtue in the interior sensitive
powers of apprehension.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, In the interior sensitive powers of apprehension there
are some habits. And this is made clear principally from what the
Philosopher says (De Memoria ii), that "in remembering one thing after
another, we become used to it; and use is a second nature." Now a habit
of use is nothing else than a habit acquired by use, which is like unto
nature. Wherefore Tully says of virtue in his Rhetoric that "it is a
habit like a second nature in accord with reason." Yet, in man, that
which he acquires by use, in his memory and other sensitive powers of
apprehension, is not a habit properly so called, but something annexed to
the habits of the intellective faculty, as we have said above (Q[50],
A[4], ad 3).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] Body Para. 2/2

Nevertheless even if there be habits in such powers, they cannot be
virtues. For virtue is a perfect habit, by which it never happens that
anything but good is done: and so virtue must needs be in that power
which consummates the good act. But the knowledge of truth is not
consummated in the sensitive powers of apprehension: for such powers
prepare the way to the intellective knowledge. And therefore in these
powers there are none of the virtues, by which we know truth: these are
rather in the intellect or reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 1: The sensitive appetite is related to the will, which is the
rational appetite, through being moved by it. And therefore the act of
the appetitive power is consummated in the sensitive appetite: and for
this reason the sensitive appetite is the subject of virtue. Whereas the
sensitive powers of apprehension are related to the intellect rather
through moving it; for the reason that the phantasms are related to the
intellective soul, as colors to sight (De Anima iii, text. 18). And
therefore the act of knowledge is terminated in the intellect; and for
this reason the cognoscitive virtues are in the intellect itself, or the
reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2

And thus is made clear the Reply to the Second Objection.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Memory is not a part of prudence, as species is of a genus,
as though memory were a virtue properly so called: but one of the
conditions required for prudence is a good memory; so that, in a fashion,
it is after the manner of an integral part.



Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the will can be the subject of virtue?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the will is not the subject of virtue. Because
no habit is required for that which belongs to a power by reason of its
very nature. But since the will is in the reason, it is of the very
essence of the will, according to the Philosopher (De Anima iii, text.
42), to tend to that which is good, according to reason. And to this good
every virtue is ordered, since everything naturally desires its own
proper good; for virtue, as Tully says in his Rhetoric, is a "habit like
a second nature in accord with reason." Therefore the will is not the
subject of virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, every virtue is either intellectual or moral (Ethic. i,
13; ii, 1). But intellectual virtue is subjected in the intellect and
reason, and not in the will: while moral virtue is subjected in the
irascible and concupiscible powers which are rational by participation.
Therefore no virtue is subjected in the will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, all human acts, to which virtues are ordained, are
voluntary. If therefore there be a virtue in the will in respect of some
human acts, in like manner there will be a virtue in the will in respect
of all human acts. Either, therefore, there will be no virtue in any
other power, or there will be two virtues ordained to the same act, which
seems unreasonable. Therefore the will cannot be the subject of virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Greater perfection is required in the mover than in the
moved. But the will moves the irascible and concupiscible powers. Much
more therefore should there be virtue in the will than in the irascible
and concupiscible powers.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Since the habit perfects the power in reference to act,
then does the power need a habit perfecting it unto doing well, which
habit is a virtue, when the power's own proper nature does not suffice
for the purpose.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] Body Para. 2/2

Now the proper nature of a power is seen in its relation to its object.
Since, therefore, as we have said above (Q[19], A[3]), the object of the
will is the good of reason proportionate to the will, in respect of this
the will does not need a virtue perfecting it. But if man's will is
confronted with a good that exceeds its capacity, whether as regards the
whole human species, such as Divine good, which transcends the limits of
human nature, or as regards the individual, such as the good of one's
neighbor, then does the will need virtue. And therefore such virtues as
those which direct man's affections to God or to his neighbor are
subjected in the will, as charity, justice, and such like.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: This objection is true of those virtues which are ordained
to the willer's own good; such as temperance and fortitude, which are
concerned with the human passions, and the like, as is clear from what
we have said (Q[35], A[6]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Not only the irascible and concupiscible powers are
rational by participation but "the appetitive power altogether," i.e. in
its entirety (Ethic. i, 13). Now the will is included in the appetitive
power. And therefore whatever virtue is in the will must be a moral
virtue, unless it be theological, as we shall see later on (Q[62], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[56] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Some virtues are directed to the good of moderated passion,
which is the proper good of this or that man: and in these cases there is
no need for virtue in the will, for the nature of the power suffices for
the purpose, as we have said. This need exists only in the case of
virtues which are directed to some extrinsic good.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License