Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT FS Prologue Para. 1/1 - FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (FS) (QQ[1]-114)
      • Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES (SIX ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES (SIX ARTICLES)

We now have to consider the various kinds of virtue: and (1) the
intellectual virtues; (2) the moral virtues; (3) the theological virtues.
Concerning the first there are six points of inquiry:

(1) Whether habits of the speculative intellect are virtues?

(2) Whether they are three, namely, wisdom, science and understanding?

(3) Whether the intellectual habit, which is art, is a virtue?

(4) Whether prudence is a virtue distinct from art?

(5) Whether prudence is a virtue necessary to man?

(6) Whether "eubulia," "synesis" and "gnome" are virtues annexed to
prudence?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the habits of the speculative intellect are virtues?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the habits of the speculative intellect are
not virtues. For virtue is an operative habit, as we have said above
(Q[55], A[2]). But speculative habits are not operative: for speculative
matter is distinct from practical, i.e. operative matter. Therefore the
habits of the speculative intellect are not virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, virtue is about those things by which man is made happy
or blessed: for "happiness is the reward of virtue" (Ethic. i, 9). Now
intellectual habits do not consider human acts or other human goods, by
which man acquires happiness, but rather things pertaining to nature or
to God. Therefore such like habits cannot be called virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, science is a speculative habit. But science and virtue
are distinct from one another as genera which are not subalternate, as
the Philosopher proves in Topic. iv. Therefore speculative habits are not
virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The speculative habits alone consider necessary things
which cannot be otherwise than they are. Now the Philosopher (Ethic. vi,
1) places certain intellectual virtues in that part of the soul which
considers necessary things that cannot be otherwise than they are.
Therefore the habits of the speculative intellect are virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Since every virtue is ordained to some good, as stated
above (Q[55], A[3]), a habit, as we have already observed (Q[56], A[3]),
may be called a virtue for two reasons: first, because it confers aptness
in doing good; secondly, because besides aptness, it confers the right
use of it. The latter condition, as above stated (Q[55], A[3]), belongs
to those habits alone which affect the appetitive part of the soul: since
it is the soul's appetitive power that puts all the powers and habits to
their respective uses.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] Body Para. 2/2

Since, then, the habits of the speculative intellect do not perfect the
appetitive part, nor affect it in any way, but only the intellective
part; they may indeed be called virtues in so far as they confer aptness
for a good work, viz. the consideration of truth (since this is the good
work of the intellect): yet they are not called virtues in the second
way, as though they conferred the right use of a power or habit. For if a
man possess a habit of speculative science, it does not follow that he is
inclined to make use of it, but he is made able to consider the truth in
those matters of which he has scientific knowledge: that he make use of
the knowledge which he has, is due to the motion of his will.
Consequently a virtue which perfects the will, as charity or justice,
confers the right use of these speculative habits. And in this way too there can be merit in the acts of these habits, if they be done out of
charity: thus Gregory says (Moral. vi) that the "contemplative life has
greater merit than the active life."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Work is of two kinds, exterior and interior. Accordingly
the practical or active faculty which is contrasted with the speculative
faculty, is concerned with exterior work, to which the speculative habit
is not ordained. Yet it is ordained to the interior act of the intellect
which is to consider the truth. And in this way it is an operative habit.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Virtue is about certain things in two ways. In the first
place a virtue is about its object. And thus these speculative virtues
are not about those things whereby man is made happy; except perhaps, in
so far as the word "whereby" indicates the efficient cause or object of
complete happiness, i.e. God, Who is the supreme object of contemplation.
Secondly, a virtue is said to be about its acts: and in this sense the
intellectual virtues are about those things whereby a man is made happy;
both because the acts of these virtues can be meritorious, as stated
above, and because they are a kind of beginning of perfect bliss, which
consists in the contemplation of truth, as we have already stated (Q[3],
A[7]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Science is contrasted with virtue taken in the second
sense, wherein it belongs to the appetitive faculty.

(tm)Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether there are only three habits of the speculative intellect, viz.
wisdom, science and understanding?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem unfitting to distinguish three virtues of the
speculative intellect, viz. wisdom, science and understanding. Because a
species is a kind of science, as stated in Ethic. vi, 7. Therefore wisdom
should not be condivided with science among the intellectual virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, in differentiating powers, habits and acts in respect of
their objects, we consider chiefly the formal aspect of these objects, as
we have already explained (FP, Q[77], A[3]). Therefore diversity of
habits is taken, not from their material objects, but from the formal
aspect of those objects. Now the principle of a demonstration is the
formal aspect under which the conclusion is known. Therefore the
understanding of principles should not be set down as a habit or virtue
distinct from the knowledge of conclusions.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, an intellectual virtue is one which resides in the
essentially rational faculty. Now even the speculative reason employs the
dialectic syllogism for the sake of argument, just as it employs the
demonstrative syllogism. Therefore as science, which is the result of a
demonstrative syllogism, is set down as an intellectual virtue, so also
should opinion be.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 1) reckons these three
alone as being intellectual virtues, viz. wisdom, science and
understanding.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As already stated (A[1]), the virtues of the speculative
intellect are those which perfect the speculative intellect for the
consideration of truth: for this is its good work. Now a truth is subject
to a twofold consideration - as known in itself, and as known through
another. What is known in itself, is as a "principle," and is at once
understood by the intellect: wherefore the habit that perfects the
intellect for the consideration of such truth is called "understanding,"
which is the habit of principles.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] Body Para. 2/2

On the other hand, a truth which is known through another, is understood
by the intellect, not at once, but by means of the reason's inquiry, and
is as a "term." This may happen in two ways: first, so that it is the
last in some particular genus; secondly, so that it is the ultimate term
of all human knowledge. And, since "things that are knowable last from
our standpoint, are knowable first and chiefly in their nature" (Phys. i,
text. 2, 3); hence that which is last with respect to all human
knowledge, is that which is knowable first and chiefly in its nature. And
about these is "wisdom," which considers the highest causes, as stated in
Metaph. i, 1,2. Wherefore it rightly judges all things and sets them in
order, because there can be no perfect and universal judgment that is not
based on the first causes. But in regard to that which is last in this
or that genus of knowable matter, it is "science" which perfects the
intellect. Wherefore according to the different kinds of knowable matter,
there are different habits of scientific knowledge; whereas there is but
one wisdom.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Wisdom is a kind of science, in so far as it has that which
is common to all the sciences; viz. to demonstrate conclusions from
principles. But since it has something proper to itself above the other
sciences, inasmuch as it judges of them all, not only as to their
conclusions, but also as to their first principles, therefore it is a
more perfect virtue than science.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 2: When the formal aspect of the object is referred to a power
or habit by one same act, there is no distinction of habit or power in
respect of the formal aspect and of the material object: thus it belongs
to the same power of sight to see both color, and light, which is the
formal aspect under which color is seen, and is seen at the same time as
the color. On the other hand, the principles of a demonstration can be
considered apart, without the conclusion being considered at all. Again
they can be considered together with the conclusions, since the
conclusions can be deduced from them. Accordingly, to consider the
principles in this second way, belongs to science, which considers the
conclusions also: while to consider the principles in themselves belongs
to understanding.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2

Consequently, if we consider the point aright, these three virtues are
distinct, not as being on a par with one another, but in a certain order.
The same is to be observed in potential wholes, wherein one part is more
perfect than another; for instance, the rational soul is more perfect
than the sensitive soul; and the sensitive, than the vegetal. For it is
thus that science depends on understanding as on a virtue of higher
degree: and both of these depend on wisdom, as obtaining the highest
place, and containing beneath itself both understanding and science, by
judging both of the conclusions of science, and of the principles on
which they are based.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: As stated above (Q[55], AA[3],4), a virtuous habit has a
fixed relation to good, and is nowise referable to evil. Now the good of
the intellect is truth, and falsehood is its evil. Wherefore those habits
alone are called intellectual virtues, whereby we tell the truth and
never tell a falsehood. But opinion and suspicion can be about both truth
and falsehood: and so, as stated in Ethic. vi, 3, they are not
intellectual virtues.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the intellectual habit, art, is a virtue?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that art is not an intellectual virtue. For
Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. ii, 18,19) that "no one makes bad use of
virtue." But one may make bad use of art: for a craftsman can work badly
according to the knowledge of his art. Therefore art is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, there is no virtue of a virtue. But "there is a virtue
of art," according to the Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 5). Therefore art is
not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the liberal arts excel the mechanical arts. But just as
the mechanical arts are practical, so the liberal arts are speculative.
Therefore, if art were an intellectual virtue, it would have to be
reckoned among the speculative virtues.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 3,4) says that art is a
virtue; and yet he does not reckon it among the speculative virtues,
which, according to him, reside in the scientific part of the soul.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Art is nothing else but "the right reason about certain
works to be made." And yet the good of these things depends, not on man's
appetitive faculty being affected in this or that way, but on the
goodness of the work done. For a craftsman, as such, is commendable, not
for the will with which he does a work, but for the quality of the work.
Art, therefore, properly speaking, is an operative habit. And yet it has
something in common with the speculative habits: since the quality of the
object considered by the latter is a matter of concern to them also, but
not how the human appetite may be affected towards that object. For as
long as the geometrician demonstrates the truth, it matters not how his
appetitive faculty may be affected, whether he be joyful or angry: even
as neither does this matter in a craftsman, as we have observed. And so
art has the nature of a virtue in the same way as the speculative habits,
in so far, to wit, as neither art nor speculative habit makes a good work
as regards the use of the habit, which is the property of a virtue that
perfects the appetite, but only as regards the aptness to work well.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: When anyone endowed with an art produces bad workmanship,
this is not the work of that art, in fact it is contrary to the art: even
as when a man lies, while knowing the truth, his words are not in accord
with his knowledge, but contrary thereto. Wherefore, just as science has
always a relation to good, as stated above (A[2], ad 3), so it is with
art: and it is for this reason that it is called a virtue. And yet it
falls short of being a perfect virtue, because it does not make its
possessor to use it well; for which purpose something further is
requisite: although there cannot be a good use without the art.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: In order that man may make good use of the art he has, he
needs a good will, which is perfected by moral virtue; and for this
reason the Philosopher says that there is a virtue of art; namely, a
moral virtue, in so far as the good use of art requires a moral virtue.
For it is evident that a craftsman is inclined by justice, which
rectifies his will, to do his work faithfully.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Even in speculative matters there is something by way of
work: e.g. the making of a syllogism or of a fitting speech, or the work
of counting or measuring. Hence whatever habits are ordained to such like
works of the speculative reason, are, by a kind of comparison, called
arts indeed, but "liberal" arts, in order to distinguish them from those
arts that are ordained to works done by the body, which arts are, in a
fashion, servile, inasmuch as the body is in servile subjection to the
soul, and man, as regards his soul, is free [liber]. On the other hand,
those sciences which are not ordained to any such like work, are called
sciences simply, and not arts. Nor, if the liberal arts be more
excellent, does it follow that the notion of art is more applicable to
them.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether prudence is a distinct virtue from art?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that prudence is not a distinct virtue from art.
For art is the right reason about certain works. But diversity of works
does not make a habit cease to be an art; since there are various arts
about works widely different. Since therefore prudence is also right
reason about works, it seems that it too should be reckoned a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, prudence has more in common with art than the
speculative habits have; for they are both "about contingent matters that
may be otherwise than they are" (Ethic. vi, 4,5). Now some speculative
habits are called arts. Much more, therefore, should prudence be called
an art.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, it belongs to prudence, "to be of good counsel" (Ethic.
vi, 5). But counselling takes place in certain arts also, as stated in
Ethic. iii, 3, e.g. in the arts of warfare, of seamanship, and of
medicine. Therefore prudence is not distinct from art.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher distinguishes prudence from art (Ethic.
vi, 5).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Where the nature of virtue differs, there is a different
kind of virtue. Now it has been stated above (A[1]; Q[56], A[3]) that
some habits have the nature of virtue, through merely conferring aptness
for a good work: while some habits are virtues, not only through
conferring aptness for a good work, but also through conferring the use.
But art confers the mere aptness for good work; since it does not regard
the appetite; whereas prudence confers not only aptness for a good work,
but also the use: for it regards the appetite, since it presupposes the
rectitude thereof.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

The reason for this difference is that art is the "right reason of
things to be made"; whereas prudence is the "right reason of things to be
done." Now "making" and "doing" differ, as stated in Metaph. ix, text.
16, in that "making" is an action passing into outward matter, e.g. "to
build," "to saw," and so forth; whereas "doing" is an action abiding in
the agent, e.g. "to see," "to will," and the like. Accordingly prudence
stands in the same relation to such like human actions, consisting in
the use of powers and habits, as art does to outward making: since each
is the perfect reason about the things with which it is concerned. But
perfection and rectitude of reason in speculative matters, depend on the
principles from which reason argues; just as we have said above (A[2], ad
2) that science depends on and presupposes understanding, which is the
habit of principles. Now in human acts the end is what the principles are
in speculative matters, as stated in Ethic. vii, 8. Consequently, it is
requisite for prudence, which is right reason about things to be done,
that man be well disposed with regard to the ends: and this depends on
the rectitude of his appetite. Wherefore, for prudence there is need of a
moral virtue, which rectifies the appetite. On the other hand the good
things made by art is not the good of man's appetite, but the good of
those things themselves: wherefore art does not presuppose rectitude of
the appetite. The consequence is that more praise is given to a craftsman
who is at fault willingly, than to one who is unwillingly; whereas it is
more contrary to prudence to sin willingly than unwillingly, since
rectitude of the will is essential to prudence, but not to art.
Accordingly it is evident that prudence is a virtue distinct from art.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The various kinds of things made by art are all external to
man: hence they do not cause a different kind of virtue. But prudence is
right reason about human acts themselves: hence it is a distinct kind of
virtue, as stated above.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Prudence has more in common with art than a speculative
habit has, if we consider their subject and matter: for they are both in
the thinking part of the soul, and about things that may be otherwise
than they are. But if we consider them as virtues, then art has more in
common with the speculative habits, as is clear from what has been said.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Prudence is of good counsel about matters regarding man's
entire life, and the end of human life. But in some arts there is counsel
about matters concerning the ends proper to those arts. Hence some men,
in so far as they are good counselors in matters of warfare, or
seamanship, are said to be prudent officers or pilots, but not simply
prudent: only those are simply prudent who give good counsel about all
the concerns of life.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether prudence is a virtue necessary to man?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that prudence is not a virtue necessary to lead a
good life. For as art is to things that are made, of which it is the
right reason, so is prudence to things that are done, in respect of which
we judge of a man's life: for prudence is the right reason about these
things, as stated in Ethic. vi, 5. Now art is not necessary in things
that are made, save in order that they be made, but not after they have
been made. Neither, therefore is prudence necessary to man in order to
lead a good life, after he has become virtuous; but perhaps only in order
that he may become virtuous.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, "It is by prudence that we are of good counsel," as
stated in Ethic. vi, 5. But man can act not only from his own, but also
from another's good counsel. Therefore man does not need prudence in
order to lead a good life, but it is enough that he follow the counsels
of prudent men.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, an intellectual virtue is one by which one always tells
the truth, and never a falsehood. But this does not seem to be the case
with prudence: for it is not human never to err in taking counsel about
what is to be done; since human actions are about things that may be
otherwise than they are. Hence it is written (Wis. 9:14): "The thoughts
of mortal men are fearful, and our counsels uncertain." Therefore it
seems that prudence should not be reckoned an intellectual virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is reckoned with other virtues necessary for human
life, when it is written (Wis. 8:7) of Divine Wisdom: "She teacheth
temperance and prudence and justice and fortitude, which are such things
as men can have nothing more profitable in life."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Prudence is a virtue most necessary for human life. For a
good life consists in good deeds. Now in order to do good deeds, it
matters not only what a man does, but also how he does it; to wit, that
he do it from right choice and not merely from impulse or passion. And,
since choice is about things in reference to the end, rectitude of choice
requires two things: namely, the due end, and something suitably ordained
to that due end. Now man is suitably directed to his due end by a virtue
which perfects the soul in the appetitive part, the object of which is
the good and the end. And to that which is suitably ordained to the due
end man needs to be rightly disposed by a habit in his reason, because
counsel and choice, which are about things ordained to the end, are acts
of the reason. Consequently an intellectual virtue is needed in the
reason, to perfect the reason, and make it suitably affected towards
things ordained to the end; and this virtue is prudence. Consequently
prudence is a virtue necessary to lead a good life.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The good of an art is to be found, not in the craftsman,
but in the product of the art, since art is right reason about things to
be made: for since the making of a thing passes into external matter, it
is a perfection not of the maker, but of the thing made, even as movement
is the act of the thing moved: and art is concerned with the making of
things. On the other hand, the good of prudence is in the active
principle, whose activity is its perfection: for prudence is right reason
about things to be done, as stated above (A[4]). Consequently art does
not require of the craftsman that his act be a good act, but that his
work be good. Rather would it be necessary for the thing made to act well
(e.g. that a knife should carve well, or that a saw should cut well), if
it were proper to such things to act, rather than to be acted on,
because they have not dominion over their actions. Wherefore the
craftsman needs art, not that he may live well, but that he may produce a
good work of art, and have it in good keeping: whereas prudence is
necessary to man, that he may lead a good life, and not merely that he
may be a good man.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: When a man does a good deed, not of his own counsel, but
moved by that of another, his deed is not yet quite perfect, as regards
his reason in directing him and his appetite in moving him. Wherefore, if
he do a good deed, he does not do well simply; and yet this is required
in order that he may lead a good life.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: As stated in Ethic. vi, 2, truth is not the same for the
practical as for the speculative intellect. Because the truth of the
speculative intellect depends on conformity between the intellect and the
thing. And since the intellect cannot be infallibly in conformity with
things in contingent matters, but only in necessary matters, therefore no
speculative habit about contingent things is an intellectual virtue, but
only such as is about necessary things. On the other hand, the truth of
the practical intellect depends on conformity with right appetite. This
conformity has no place in necessary matters, which are not affected by
the human will; but only in contingent matters which can be effected by
us, whether they be matters of interior action, or the products of
external work. Hence it is only about contingent matters that an
intellectual virtue is assigned to the practical intellect, viz. art, as
regards things to be made, and prudence, as regards things to be done.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether "eubulia, synesis, and gnome" are virtues annexed to prudence?
[*{euboulia, synesis, gnome}]

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that "{euboulia, synesis}, and {gnome}" are
unfittingly assigned as virtues annexed to prudence. For "{euboulia}" is
"a habit whereby we take good counsel" (Ethic. vi, 9). Now it "belongs to
prudence to take good counsel," as stated (Ethic. vi, 9). Therefore
"{euboulia}" is not a virtue annexed to prudence, but rather is prudence
itself.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, it belongs to the higher to judge the lower. The highest
virtue would therefore seem to be the one whose act is judgment. Now
"{synesis}" enables us to judge well. Therefore "{synesis}" is not a
virtue annexed to prudence, but rather is a principal virtue.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, just as there are various matters to pass judgment on,
so are there different points on which one has to take counsel. But there
is one virtue referring to all matters of counsel. Therefore, in order to
judge well of what has to be done, there is no need, besides "{synesis}"
of the virtue of "{gnome}."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, Cicero (De Invent. Rhet. iii) mentions three other parts of prudence; viz. "memory of the past, understanding of the
present, and foresight of the future." Moreover, Macrobius (Super Somn.
Scip. 1) mentions yet others: viz. "caution, docility," and the like.
Therefore it seems that the above are not the only virtues annexed to
prudence.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, stands the authority of the Philosopher (Ethic. vi,
9,10,11), who assigns these three virtues as being annexed to prudence.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Wherever several powers are subordinate to one another,
that power is the highest which is ordained to the highest act. Now there
are three acts of reason in respect of anything done by man: the first of
these is counsel; the second, judgment; the third, command. The first two
correspond to those acts of the speculative intellect, which are inquiry
and judgment, for counsel is a kind of inquiry: but the third is proper
to the practical intellect, in so far as this is ordained to operation;
for reason does not have to command in things that man cannot do. Now it
is evident that in things done by man, the chief act is that of command,
to which all the rest are subordinate. Consequently, that virtue which
perfects the command, viz. prudence, as obtaining the highest place, has
other secondary virtues annexed to it, viz. "{eustochia}," which perfects
counsel; and "{synesis}" and "{gnome}," which are parts of prudence in
relation to judgment, and of whose distinction we shall speak further on
(ad 3).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Prudence makes us be of good counsel, not as though its
immediate act consisted in being of good counsel, but because it perfects
the latter act by means of a subordinate virtue, viz. "{euboulia}."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Judgment about what is to be done is directed to something
further: for it may happen in some matter of action that a man's judgment
is sound, while his execution is wrong. The matter does not attain to its
final complement until the reason has commanded aright in the point of
what has to be done.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Judgment of anything should be based on that thing's proper
principles. But inquiry does not reach to the proper principles: because,
if we were in possession of these, we should need no more to inquire, the
truth would be already discovered. Hence only one virtue is directed to
being of good counsel, wheres there are two virtues for good judgment:
because difference is based not on common but on proper principles.
Consequently, even in speculative matters, there is one science of
dialectics, which inquires about all matters; whereas demonstrative
sciences, which pronounce judgment, differ according to their different
objects. "{Synesis}" and "{gnome}" differ in respect of the different
rules on which judgment is based: for "{synesis}" judges of actions according to the common law; while "{gnome}" bases its judgment on the
natural law, in those cases where the common law fails to apply, as we
shall explain further on (SS, Q[51], A[4]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[57] A[6] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Memory, understanding and foresight, as also caution and
docility and the like, are not virtues distinct from prudence: but are,
as it were, integral parts thereof, in so far as they are all requisite
for perfect prudence. There are, moreover, subjective parts or species of
prudence, e.g. domestic and political economy, and the like. But the
three first names are, in a fashion, potential parts of prudence; because
they are subordinate thereto, as secondary virtues to a principal virtue:
and we shall speak of them later (SS, Q[48], seqq.).





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License