Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT FS Prologue Para. 1/1 - FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (FS) (QQ[1]-114)
      • Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] Out. Para. 1/2 - OF VENIAL AND MORTAL SIN (SIX ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] Out. Para. 1/2 - OF VENIAL AND MORTAL SIN (SIX ARTICLES)

In the next place, since venial and mortal sins differ in respect of the
debt of punishment, we must consider them. First, we shall consider
venial sin as compared with mortal sin; secondly, we shall consider
venial sin in itself.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] Out. Para. 2/2

Under the first head there are six points of inquiry:

(1) Whether venial sin is fittingly condivided with mortal sin?

(2) Whether they differ generically?

(3) Whether venial sin is a disposition to mortal sin?

(4) Whether a venial sin can become mortal?

(5) Whether a venial sin can become mortal by reason of an aggravating
circumstance?

(6) Whether a mortal sin can become venial?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether venial sin is fittingly condivided with mortal sin?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that venial sin is unfittingly condivided with
mortal sin. For Augustine says (Contra Faust. xxii, 27): "Sin is a word,
deed or desire contrary to the eternal law." But the fact of being
against the eternal law makes a sin to be mortal. Consequently every sin
is mortal. Therefore venial sin is not condivided with mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Apostle says (1 Cor. 10:31): "Whether you eat or
drink, or whatever else you do; do all to the glory of God." Now whoever
sins breaks this commandment, because sin is not done for God's glory.
Consequently, since to break a commandment is to commit a mortal sin, it
seems that whoever sins, sins mortally.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, whoever cleaves to a thing by love, cleaves either as
enjoying it, or as using it, as Augustine states (De Doctr. Christ. i,
3,4). But no person, in sinning, cleaves to a mutable good as using it:
because he does not refer it to that good which gives us happiness,
which, properly speaking, is to use, according to Augustine (De Doctr.
Christ. i, 3,4). Therefore whoever sins enjoys a mutable good. Now "to
enjoy what we should use is human perverseness," as Augustine again says
(Qq. lxxxiii, qu. 30). Therefore, since "perverseness" [*The Latin
'pervertere' means to overthrow, to destroy, hence 'perversion' of God's
law is a mortal sin.] denotes a mortal sin, it seems that whoever sins,
sins mortally.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, whoever approaches one term, from that very fact turns
away from the opposite. Now whoever sins, approaches a mutable good, and,
consequently turns away from the immutable good, so that he sins
mortally. Therefore venial sin is unfittingly condivided with mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (Tract. xli in Joan.), that "a crime is
one that merits damnation, and a venial sin, one that does not." But a
crime denotes a mortal sin. Therefore venial sin is fittingly condivided
with mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, Certain terms do not appear to be mutually opposed, if
taken in their proper sense, whereas they are opposed if taken
metaphorically: thus "to smile" is not opposed to "being dry"; but if we
speak of the smiling meadows when they are decked with flowers and fresh
with green hues this is opposed to drought. In like manner if mortal be
taken literally as referring to the death of the body, it does not imply
opposition to venial, nor belong to the same genus. But if mortal be
taken metaphorically, as applied to sin, it is opposed to that which is
venial.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Body Para. 2/3

For sin, being a sickness of the soul, as stated above (Q[71], A[1], ad
3; Q[72], A[5]; Q[74], A[9], ad 2), is said to be mortal by comparison
with a disease, which is said to be mortal, through causing an
irreparable defect consisting in the corruption of a principle, as stated
above (Q[72], A[5]). Now the principle of the spiritual life, which is a
life in accord with virtue, is the order to the last end, as stated above
(Q[72], A[5]; Q[87], A[3]): and if this order be corrupted, it cannot be
repaired by any intrinsic principle, but by the power of God alone, as
stated above (Q[87], A[3]), because disorders in things referred to the
end, are repaired through the end, even as an error about conclusions can
be repaired through the truth of the principles. Hence the defect of
order to the last end cannot be repaired through something else as a
higher principle, as neither can an error about principles. Wherefore
such sins are called mortal, as being irreparable. On the other hand,
sins which imply a disorder in things referred to the end, the order to
the end itself being preserved, are reparable. These sins are called
venial: because a sin receives its acquittal [veniam] when the debt of
punishment is taken away, and this ceases when the sin ceases, as
explained above (Q[87], A[6]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] Body Para. 3/3

Accordingly, mortal and venial are mutually opposed as reparable and
irreparable: and I say this with reference to the intrinsic principle,
but not to the Divine power, which can repair all diseases, whether of
the body or of the soul. Therefore venial sin is fittingly condivided
with mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The division of sin into venial and mortal is not a
division of a genus into its species which have an equal share of the
generic nature: but it is the division of an analogous term into its
parts, of which it is predicated, of the one first, and of the other
afterwards. Consequently the perfect notion of sin, which Augustine
gives, applies to mortal sin. On the other hand, venial sin is called a
sin, in reference to an imperfect notion of sin, and in relation to
mortal sin: even as an accident is called a being, in relation to
substance, in reference to the imperfect notion of being. For it is not
"against" the law, since he who sins venially neither does what the law
forbids, nor omits what the law prescribes to be done; but he acts
"beside" the law, through not observing the mode of reason, which the law
intends.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: This precept of the Apostle is affirmative, and so it does
not bind for all times. Consequently everyone who does not actually refer
all his actions to the glory of God, does not therefore act against this
precept. In order, therefore, to avoid mortal sin each time that one
fails actually to refer an action to God's glory, it is enough to refer
oneself and all that one has to God habitually. Now venial sin excludes
only actual reference of the human act to God's glory, and not habitual
reference: because it does not exclude charity, which refers man to God
habitually. Therefore it does not follow that he who sins venially, sins
mortally.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: He that sins venially, cleaves to temporal good, not as
enjoying it, because he does not fix his end in it, but as using it, by
referring it to God, not actually but habitually.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Mutable good is not considered to be a term in
contraposition to the immutable good, unless one's end is fixed therein:
because what is referred to the end has not the character of finality.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether mortal and venial sin differ generically?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that venial and mortal sin do not differ
generically, so that some sins be generically mortal, and some
generically venial. Because human acts are considered to be generically
good or evil according to their matter or object, as stated above (Q[18],
A[2]). Now either mortal or venial sin may be committed in regard to any
object or matter: since man can love any mutable good, either less than
God, which may be a venial sin, or more than God, which is a mortal sin.
Therefore venial and mortal sin do not differ generically.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, as stated above (A[1]; Q[72], A[5]; Q[87], A[3]), a sin
is called mortal when it is irreparable, venial when it can be repaired.
Now irreparability belongs to sin committed out of malice, which,
according to some, is irremissible: whereas reparability belongs to sins
committed through weakness or ignorance, which are remissible. Therefore
mortal and venial sin differ as sin committed through malice differs from
sin committed through weakness or ignorance. But, in this respect, sins
differ not in genus but in cause, as stated above (Q[77], A[8], ad 1).
Therefore venial and mortal sin do not differ generically.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, it was stated above (Q[74], A[3], ad 3; A[10]) that
sudden movements both of the sensuality and of the reason are venial
sins. But sudden movements occur in every kind of sin. Therefore no sins
are generically venial.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine, in a sermon on Purgatory (De Sanctis, serm.
xli), enumerates certain generic venial sins, and certain generic mortal
sins.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, Venial sin is so called from "venia" [pardon].
Consequently a sin may be called venial, first of all, because it has
been pardoned: thus Ambrose says that "penance makes every sin venial":
and this is called venial "from the result." Secondly, a sin is called
venial because it does not contain anything either partially or totally,
to prevent its being pardoned: partially, as when a sin contains
something diminishing its guilt, e.g. a sin committed through weakness or
ignorance: and this is called venial "from the cause": totally, through
not destroying the order to the last end, wherefore it deserves temporal,
but not everlasting punishment. It is of this venial sin that we wish to
speak now.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Body Para. 2/3

For as regards the first two, it is evident that they have no
determinate genus: whereas venial sin, taken in the third sense, can have
a determinate genus, so that one sin may be venial generically, and
another generically mortal, according as the genus or species of an act
is determined by its object. For, when the will is directed to a thing
that is in itself contrary to charity, whereby man is directed to his
last end, the sin is mortal by reason of its object. Consequently it is a
mortal sin generically, whether it be contrary to the love of God, e.g.
blasphemy, perjury, and the like, or against the love of one's neighbor,
e.g. murder, adultery, and such like: wherefore such sins are mortal by
reason of their genus. Sometimes, however, the sinner's will is directed
to a thing containing a certain inordinateness, but which is not contrary
to the love of God and one's neighbor, e.g. an idle word, excessive
laughter, and so forth: and such sins are venial by reason of their genus.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] Body Para. 3/3

Nevertheless, since moral acts derive their character of goodness and
malice, not only from their objects, but also from some disposition of
the agent, as stated above (Q[18], AA[4],6), it happens sometimes that a
sin which is venial generically by reason of its object, becomes mortal
on the part of the agent, either because he fixes his last end therein,
or because he directs it to something that is a mortal sin in its own
genus; for example, if a man direct an idle word to the commission of
adultery. In like manner it may happen, on the part of the agent, that a
sin generically mortal because venial, by reason of the act being
imperfect, i.e. not deliberated by reason, which is the proper principle
of an evil act, as we have said above in reference to sudden movements of
unbelief.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The very fact that anyone chooses something that is
contrary to divine charity, proves that he prefers it to the love of God,
and consequently, that he loves it more than he loves God. Hence it
belongs to the genus of some sins, which are of themselves contrary to
charity, that something is loved more than God; so that they are mortal
by reason of their genus.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: This argument considers those sins which are venial from
their cause.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: This argument considers those sins which are venial by
reason of the imperfection of the act.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether venial sin is a disposition to mortal sin?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that venial sin is not a disposition to mortal sin.
For one contrary does not dispose to another. But venial and mortal sin
are condivided as contrary to one another, as stated above (A[1]).
Therefore venial sin is not a disposition to mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, an act disposes to something of like species, wherefore
it is stated in Ethic. ii, 1,2, that "from like acts like dispositions
and habits are engendered." But mortal and venial sin differ in genus or
species, as stated above (A[2]). Therefore venial sin does not dispose to
mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, if a sin is called venial because it disposes to mortal
sin, it follows that whatever disposes to mortal sin is a venial sin. Now
every good work disposes to mortal sin; wherefore Augustine says in his
Rule (Ep. ccxi) that "pride lies in wait for good works that it may
destroy them." Therefore even good works would be venial sins, which is
absurd.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (Ecclus. 19:1): "He that contemneth small
things shall fall by little and little." Now he that sins venially seems
to contemn small things. Therefore by little and little he is disposed to
fall away together into mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, A disposition is a kind of cause; wherefore as there is a
twofold manner of cause, so is there a twofold manner of disposition.
For there is a cause which moves directly to the production of the
effect, as a hot thing heats: and there is a cause which moves
indirectly, by removing an obstacle, as he who displaces a pillar is said
to displace the stone that rests on it. Accordingly an act of sin
disposes to something in two ways. First, directly, and thus it disposes
to an act of like species. In this way, a sin generically venial does
not, primarily and of its nature, dispose to a sin generically mortal,
for they differ in species. Nevertheless, in this same way, a venial sin
can dispose, by way of consequence, to a sin which is mortal on the part
of the agent: because the disposition or habit may be so far strengthened
by acts of venial sin, that the lust of sinning increases, and the sinner
fixes his end in that venial sin: since the end for one who has a habit,
as such, is to work according to that habit; and the consequence will be
that, by sinning often venially, he becomes disposed to a mortal sin.
Secondly, a human act disposes to something by removing an obstacle
thereto. In this way a sin generically venial can dispose to a sin generically mortal. Because he that commits a sin generically venial,
turns aside from some particular order; and through accustoming his will
not to be subject to the due order in lesser matters, is disposed not to
subject his will even to the order of the last end, by choosing something
that is a mortal sin in its genus.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Venial and mortal sin are not condivided in contrariety to
one another, as though they were species of one genus, as stated above
(A[1], ad 1), but as an accident is condivided with substance. Wherefore
an accident can be a disposition to a substantial form, so can a venial
sin dispose to mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Venial sin is not like mortal sin in species; but it is in
genus, inasmuch as they both imply a defect of due order, albeit in
different ways, as stated (AA[1],2).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: A good work is not, of itself, a disposition to mortal sin;
but it can be the matter or occasion of mortal sin accidentally; whereas
a venial sin, of its very nature, disposes to mortal sin, as stated.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a venial sin can become mortal?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that a venial sin can become a mortal sin. For
Augustine in explaining the words of Jn. 3:36: "He that believeth not the
Son, shall not see life," says (Tract. xii in Joan.): "The slightest,"
i.e. venial, "sins kill if we make little of them." Now a sin is called
mortal through causing the spiritual death of the soul. Therefore a
venial sin can become mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a movement in the sensuality before the consent of
reason, is a venial sin, but after consent, is a mortal sin, as stated
above (Q[74], A[8], ad 2). Therefore a venial sin can become mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, venial and mortal sin differ as curable and incurable
disease, as stated above (A[1]). But a curable disease may become
incurable. Therefore a venial sin may become mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, a disposition may become a habit. Now venial sin is a
disposition to mortal, as stated (A[3]). Therefore a venial sin can
become mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Body Para. 1/4

I answer that, The fact of a venial sin becoming a mortal sin may be
understood in three ways. First, so that the same identical act be at
first a venial, and then a mortal sin. This is impossible: because a sin,
like any moral act, consists chiefly in an act of the will: so that an
act is not one morally, if the will be changed, although the act be
continuous physically. If, however, the will be not changed, it is not
possible for a venial sin to become mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Body Para. 2/4

Secondly, this may be taken to mean that a sin generically venial,
becomes mortal. This is possible, in so far as one may fix one's end in
that venial sin, or direct it to some mortal sin as end, as stated above
(A[2]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Body Para. 3/4

Thirdly, this may be understood in the sense of many venial sins
constituting one mortal sin. If this be taken as meaning that many venial
sins added together make one mortal sin, it is false, because all the
venial sins in the world cannot incur a debt of punishment equal to that
of one mortal sin. This is evident as regards the duration of the
punishment, since mortal sin incurs a debt of eternal punishment, while
venial sin incurs a debt of temporal punishment, as stated above (Q[87],
AA[3],5). It is also evident as regards the pain of loss, because mortal
sins deserve to be punished by the privation of seeing God, to which no
other punishment is comparable, as Chrysostom states (Hom. xxiv in
Matth.). It is also evident as regards the pain of sense, as to the
remorse of conscience; although as to the pain of fire, the punishments
may perhaps not be improportionate to one another.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] Body Para. 4/4

If, however, this be taken as meaning that many venial sins make one
mortal sin dispositively, it is true, as was shown above (A[3]) with
regard to the two different manners of disposition, whereby venial sin
disposes to mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Augustine is referring to the fact of many venial sins
making one mortal sin dispositively.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The same movement of the sensuality which preceded the
consent of reason can never become a mortal sin; but the movement of the
reason in consenting is a mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Disease of the body is not an act, but an abiding
disposition; wherefore, while remaining the same disease, it may undergo
change. On the other hand, venial sin is a transient act, which cannot be
taken up again: so that in this respect the comparison fails.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: A disposition that becomes a habit, is like an imperfect
thing in the same species; thus imperfect science, by being perfected,
becomes a habit. On the other hand, venial sin is a disposition to
something differing generically, even as an accident which disposes to a
substantial form, into which it is never changed.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a circumstance can make a venial sin to be mortal?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that a circumstance can make a venial sin mortal.
For Augustine says in a sermon on Purgatory (De Sanctis, serm. xli) that
"if anger continue for a long time, or if drunkenness be frequent, they
become mortal sins." But anger and drunkenness are not mortal but venial
sins generically, else they would always be mortal sins. Therefore a
circumstance makes a venial sin to be mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Master says ( Sentent. ii, D, 24) that delectation,
if morose [*See Q[74], A[6]], is a mortal sin, but that if it be not
morose, it is a venial sin. Now moroseness is a circumstance. Therefore a
circumstance makes a venial sin to be mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, evil and good differ more than venial and mortal sin,
both of which are generically evil. But a circumstance makes a good act
to be evil, as when a man gives an alms for vainglory. Much more,
therefore, can it make a venial sin to be mortal.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Since a circumstance is an accident, its quantity
cannot exceed that of the act itself, derived from the act's genus,
because the subject always excels its accident. If, therefore, an act be
venial by reason of its genus, it cannot become mortal by reason of an
accident: since, in a way, mortal sin infinitely surpasses the quantity
of venial sin, as is evident from what has been said (Q[72], A[5], ad 1;
Q[87], A[5], ad 1).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (Q[7], A[1]; Q[18], A[5], ad 4; AA[10]
,11), when we were treating of circumstances, a circumstance, as such, is
an accident of the moral act: and yet a circumstance may happen to be
taken as the specific difference of a moral act, and then it loses its
nature of circumstance, and constitutes the species of the moral act.
This happens in sins when a circumstance adds the deformity of another
genus; thus when a man has knowledge of another woman than his wife, the
deformity of his act is opposed to chastity; but if this other be another
man's wife, there is an additional deformity opposed to justice which
forbids one to take what belongs to another; and accordingly this
circumstance constitutes a new species of sin known as adultery.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] Body Para. 2/2

It is, however, impossible for a circumstance to make a venial sin
become mortal, unless it adds the deformity of another species. For it
has been stated above (A[1]) that the deformity of a venial sin consists
in a disorder affecting things that are referred to the end, whereas the
deformity of a mortal sin consists in a disorder about the last end.
Consequently it is evident that a circumstance cannot make a venial sin
to be mortal, so long as it remains a circumstance, but only when it
transfers the sin to another species, and becomes, as it were, the
specific difference of the moral act.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/3

Reply OBJ 1: Length of time is not a circumstance that draws a sin to
another species, nor is frequency or custom, except perhaps by something
accidental supervening. For an action does not acquire a new species
through being repeated or prolonged, unless by chance something supervene
in the repeated or prolonged act to change its species, e.g.
disobedience, contempt, or the like.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 2/3

We must therefore reply to the objection by saying that since anger is a
movement of the soul tending to the hurt of one's neighbor, if the angry
movement tend to a hurt which is a mortal sin generically, such as murder
or robbery, that anger will be a mortal sin generically: and if it be a
venial sin, this will be due to the imperfection of the act, in so far as
it is a sudden movement of the sensuality: whereas, if it last a long
time, it returns to its generic nature, through the consent of reason.
If, on the other hand, the hurt to which the angry movement tends, is a
sin generically venial, for instance, if a man be angry with someone, so
as to wish to say some trifling word in jest that would hurt him a
little, the anger will not be mortal sin, however long it last, unless
perhaps accidentally; for instance, if it were to give rise to great
scandal or something of the kind.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 3/3

With regard to drunkenness we reply that it is a mortal sin by reason of
its genus; for, that a man, without necessity, and through the mere lust
of wine, make himself unable to use his reason, whereby he is directed to
God and avoids committing many sins, is expressly contrary to virtue.
That it be a venial sin, is due some sort of ignorance or weakness, as
when a man is ignorant of the strength of the wine, or of his own
unfitness, so that he has no thought of getting drunk, for in that case
the drunkenness is not imputed to him as a sin, but only the excessive
drink. If, however, he gets drunk frequently, this ignorance no longer
avails as an excuse, for his will seems to choose to give way to
drunkenness rather than to refrain from excess of wine: wherefore the sin
returns to its specific nature.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Morose delectation is not a mortal sin except in those
matters which are mortal sins generically. In such matters, if the
delectation be not morose, there is a venial sin through imperfection of
the act, as we have said with regard to anger (ad 1): because anger is
said to be lasting, and delectation to be morose, on account of the
approval of the deliberating reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: A circumstance does not make a good act to be evil, unless
it constitute the species of a sin, as we have stated above (Q[18], A[5]
, ad 4).


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a mortal sin can become venial?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that a mortal sin can become venial. Because venial
sin is equally distant from mortal, as mortal sin is from venial. But a
venial sin can become mortal, as stated above (A[5]). Therefore also a
mortal sin can become venial.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, venial and mortal sin are said to differ in this, that
he who sins mortally loves a creature more than God, while he who sins
venially loves the creature less than God. Now it may happen that a
person in committing a sin generically mortal, loves a creature less than
God; for instance, if anyone being ignorant that simple fornication is a
mortal sin, and contrary to the love of God, commits the sin of
fornication, yet so as to be ready, for the love of God, to refrain from
that sin if he knew that by committing it he was acting counter to the
love of God. Therefore his will be a venial sin; and accordingly a mortal
sin can become venial.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, as stated above (A[5], OBJ[3]), good is more distant
from evil, than venial from mortal sin. But an act which is evil in
itself, can become good; thus to kill a man may be an act of justice, as
when a judge condemns a thief to death. Much more therefore can a mortal
sin become venial.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, An eternal thing can never become temporal. But mortal
sin deserves eternal punishment, whereas venial sin deserves temporal
punishment. Therefore a mortal sin can never become venial.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Venial and mortal differ as perfect and imperfect in the
genus of sin, as stated above (A[1], ad 1). Now the imperfect can become
perfect, by some sort of addition: and, consequently, a venial sin can
become mortal, by the addition of some deformity pertaining to the genus
of mortal sin, as when a man utters an idle word for the purpose of
fornication. On the other hand, the perfect cannot become imperfect, by
addition; and so a mortal sin cannot become venial, by the addition of a
deformity pertaining to the genus of venial sin, for the sin is not
diminished if a man commit fornication in order to utter an idle word;
rather is it aggravated by the additional deformity.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] Body Para. 2/2

Nevertheless a sin which is generically mortal, can become venial by
reason of the imperfection of the act, because then it does not
completely fulfil the conditions of a moral act, since it is not a
deliberate, but a sudden act, as is evident from what we have said above
(A[2]). This happens by a kind of subtraction, namely, of deliberate
reason. And since a moral act takes its species from deliberate reason,
the result is that by such a subtraction the species of the act is
destroyed.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Venial differs from mortal as imperfect from perfect, even
as a boy differs from a man. But the boy becomes a man and not vice
versa. Hence the argument does not prove.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: If the ignorance be such as to excuse sin altogether, as
the ignorance of a madman or an imbecile, then he that commits
fornication in a state of such ignorance, commits no sin either mortal or
venial. But if the ignorance be not invincible, then the ignorance itself
is a sin, and contains within itself the lack of the love of God, in so
far as a man neglects to learn those things whereby he can safeguard
himself in the love of God.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[88] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: As Augustine says (Contra Mendacium vii), "those things
which are evil in themselves, cannot be well done for any good end." Now
murder is the slaying of the innocent, and this can nowise be well done.
But, as Augustine states (De Lib. Arb. i, 4,5), the judge who sentences a
thief to death, or the soldier who slays the enemy of the common weal,
are not murderers.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License