Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] Out. Para. 1/2 - OF THE VIRTUE ITSELF OF FAITH (EIGHT ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] Out. Para. 1/2 - OF THE VIRTUE ITSELF OF FAITH (EIGHT ARTICLES)

We must now consider the virtue itself of faith, and, in the first
place, faith itself; secondly, those who have faith; thirdly, the cause
of faith; fourthly, its effects.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] Out. Para. 2/2

Under the first head there are eight points of inquiry:

(1) What is faith?

(2) In what power of the soul does it reside?

(3) Whether its form is charity?

(4) Whether living [formata] faith and lifeless [informis] faith are one
identically?

(5) Whether faith is a virtue?

(6) Whether it is one virtue?

(7) Of its relation to the other virtues;

(8) Of its certitude as compared with the certitude of the intellectual
virtues.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether this is a fitting definition of faith: "Faith is the substance of
things to be hoped for, the evidence of things that appear not?"

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the Apostle gives an unfitting definition of
faith (Heb. 11:1) when he says: "Faith is the substance of things to be
hoped for, the evidence of things that appear not." For no quality is a
substance: whereas faith is a quality, since it is a theological virtue,
as stated above (FS, Q[62], A[3]). Therefore it is not a substance.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, different virtues have different objects. Now things to
be hoped for are the object of hope. Therefore they should not be
included in a definition of faith, as though they were its object.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, faith is perfected by charity rather than by hope, since
charity is the form of faith, as we shall state further on (A[3]).
Therefore the definition of faith should have included the thing to be
loved rather than the thing to be hoped for.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, the same thing should not be placed in different genera.
Now "substance" and "evidence" are different genera, and neither is
subalternate to the other. Therefore it is unfitting to state that faith
is both "substance" and "evidence."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, evidence manifests the truth of the matter for which it
is adduced. Now a thing is said to be apparent when its truth is already
manifest. Therefore it seems to imply a contradiction to speak of
"evidence of things that appear not": and so faith is unfittingly defined.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The authority of the Apostle suffices.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 1/5

I answer that, Though some say that the above words of the Apostle are
not a definition of faith, yet if we consider the matter aright, this
definition overlooks none of the points in reference to which faith can
be defined, albeit the words themselves are not arranged in the form of a
definition, just as the philosophers touch on the principles of the
syllogism, without employing the syllogistic form.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 2/5

In order to make this clear, we must observe that since habits are known
by their acts, and acts by their objects, faith, being a habit, should
be defined by its proper act in relation to its proper object. Now the
act of faith is to believe, as stated above (Q[2], AA[2],3), which is an
act of the intellect determinate to one object of the will's command.
Hence an act of faith is related both to the object of the will, i.e. to
the good and the end, and to the object of the intellect, i.e. to the
true. And since faith, through being a theological virtues, as stated
above (FS, Q[62], A[2]), has one same thing for object and end, its
object and end must, of necessity, be in proportion to one another. Now
it has been already stated (Q[1], AA[1],4) that the object of faith is
the First Truth, as unseen, and whatever we hold on account thereof: so
that it must needs be under the aspect of something unseen that the First
Truth is the end of the act of faith, which aspect is that of a thing
hoped for, according to the Apostle (Rm. 8:25): "We hope for that which
we see not": because to see the truth is to possess it. Now one hopes not
for what one has already, but for what one has not, as stated above (FS,
Q[67], A[4]). Accordingly the relation of the act of faith to its end
which is the object of the will, is indicated by the words: "Faith is the
substance of things to be hoped for." For we are wont to call by the name
of substance, the first beginning of a thing, especially when the whole
subsequent thing is virtually contained in the first beginning; for
instance, we might say that the first self-evident principles are the
substance of science, because, to wit, these principles are in us the
first beginnings of science, the whole of which is itself contained in
them virtually. In this way then faith is said to be the "substance of
things to be hoped for," for the reason that in us the first beginning of
things to be hoped for is brought about by the assent of faith, which
contains virtually all things to be hoped for. Because we hope to be made
happy through seeing the unveiled truth to which our faith cleaves, as
was made evident when we were speaking of happiness (FS, Q[3], A[8]; FS,
Q[4], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 3/5

The relationship of the act of faith to the object of the intellect,
considered as the object of faith, is indicated by the words, "evidence
of things that appear not," where "evidence" is taken for the result of
evidence. For evidence induces the intellect to adhere to a truth,
wherefore the firm adhesion of the intellect to the non-apparent truth of
faith is called "evidence" here. Hence another reading has "conviction,"
because to wit, the intellect of the believer is convinced by Divine
authority, so as to assent to what it sees not. Accordingly if anyone
would reduce the foregoing words to the form of a definition, he may say
that "faith is a habit of the mind, whereby eternal life is begun in us,
making the intellect assent to what is non-apparent."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 4/5

In this way faith is distinguished from all other things pertaining to
the intellect. For when we describe it as "evidence," we distinguish it
from opinion, suspicion, and doubt, which do not make the intellect
adhere to anything firmly; when we go on to say, "of things that appear
not," we distinguish it from science and understanding, the object of
which is something apparent; and when we say that it is "the substance of
things to be hoped for," we distinguish the virtue of faith from faith
commonly so called, which has no reference to the beatitude we hope for.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 5/5

Whatever other definitions are given of faith, are explanations of this
one given by the Apostle. For when Augustine says (Tract. xl in Joan.:
QQ. Evang. ii, qu. 39) that "faith is a virtue whereby we believe what we
do not see," and when Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iv, 11) that "faith
is an assent without research," and when others say that "faith is that
certainty of the mind about absent things which surpasses opinion but
falls short of science," these all amount to the same as the Apostle's
words: "Evidence of things that appear not"; and when Dionysius says
(Div. Nom. vii) that "faith is the solid foundation of the believer,
establishing him in the truth, and showing forth the truth in him," comes
to the same as "substance of things to be hoped for."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: "Substance" here does not stand for the supreme genus
condivided with the other genera, but for that likeness to substance
which is found in each genus, inasmuch as the first thing in a genus
contains the others virtually and is said to be the substance thereof.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Since faith pertains to the intellect as commanded by the
will, it must needs be directed, as to its end, to the objects of those
virtues which perfect the will, among which is hope, as we shall prove
further on (Q[18], A[1]). For this reason the definition of faith
includes the object of hope.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Love may be of the seen and of the unseen, of the present
and of the absent. Consequently a thing to be loved is not so adapted to
faith, as a thing to be hoped for, since hope is always of the absent and
the unseen.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: "Substance" and "evidence" as included in the definition of
faith, do not denote various genera of faith, nor different acts, but
different relationships of one act to different objects, as is clear from
what has been said.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: Evidence taken from the proper principles of a thing, make
it apparent, whereas evidence taken from Divine authority does not make a
thing apparent in itself, and such is the evidence referred to in the
definition of faith.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether faith resides in the intellect?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that faith does not reside in the intellect. For
Augustine says (De Praedest. Sanct. v) that "faith resides in the
believer's will." Now the will is a power distinct from the intellect.
Therefore faith does not reside in the intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the assent of faith to believe anything, proceeds from
the will obeying God. Therefore it seems that faith owes all its praise
to obedience. Now obedience is in the will. Therefore faith is in the
will, and not in the intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the intellect is either speculative or practical. Now
faith is not in the speculative intellect, since this is not concerned
with things to be sought or avoided, as stated in De Anima iii, 9, so
that it is not a principle of operation, whereas "faith . . . worketh by
charity" (Gal. 5:6). Likewise, neither is it in the practical intellect,
the object of which is some true, contingent thing, that can be made or
done. For the object of faith is the Eternal Truth, as was shown above
(Q[1], A[1]). Therefore faith does not reside in the intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Faith is succeeded by the heavenly vision, according to
1 Cor. 13:12: "We see now through a glass in a dark manner; but then face
to face." Now vision is in the intellect. Therefore faith is likewise.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Since faith is a virtue, its act must needs be perfect.
Now, for the perfection of an act proceeding from two active principles,
each of these principles must be perfect: for it is not possible for a
thing to be sawn well, unless the sawyer possess the art, and the saw be
well fitted for sawing. Now, in a power of the soul, which is related to
opposite objects, a disposition to act well is a habit, as stated above
(FS, Q[49], A[4], ad 1,2,3). Wherefore an act that proceeds from two such
powers must be perfected by a habit residing in each of them. Again, it
has been stated above (Q[2], AA[1],2) that to believe is an act of the
intellect inasmuch as the will moves it to assent. And this act proceeds
from the will and the intellect, both of which have a natural aptitude to
be perfected in this way. Consequently, if the act of faith is to be
perfect, there needs to be a habit in the will as well as in the
intellect: even as there needs to be the habit of prudence in the reason,
besides the habit of temperance in the concupiscible faculty, in order
that the act of that faculty be perfect. Now, to believe is immediately
an act of the intellect, because the object of that act is "the true,"
which pertains properly to the intellect. Consequently faith, which is
the proper principle of that act, must needs reside in the intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Augustine takes faith for the act of faith, which is
described as depending on the believer's will, in so far as his intellect
assents to matters of faith at the command of the will.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Not only does the will need to be ready to obey but also
the intellect needs to be well disposed to follow the command of the
will, even as the concupiscible faculty needs to be well disposed in
order to follow the command of reason; hence there needs to be a habit of
virtue not only in the commanding will but also in the assenting
intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Faith resides in the speculative intellect, as evidenced by
its object. But since this object, which is the First Truth, is the end
of all our desires and actions, as Augustine proves (De Trin. i, 8), it
follows that faith worketh by charity just as "the speculative intellect
becomes practical by extension" (De Anima iii, 10).


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether charity is the form of faith?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that charity is not the form of faith. For each
thing derives its species from its form. When therefore two things are
opposite members of a division, one cannot be the form of the other. Now
faith and charity are stated to be opposite members of a division, as
different species of virtue (1 Cor. 13:13). Therefore charity is not the
form of faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a form and the thing of which it is the form are in one
subject, since together they form one simply. Now faith is in the
intellect, while charity is in the will. Therefore charity is not the
form of faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the form of a thing is a principle thereof. Now
obedience, rather than charity, seems to be the principle of believing,
on the part of the will, according to Rm. 1:5: "For obedience to the
faith in all nations." Therefore obedience rather than charity, is the
form of faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Each thing works through its form. Now faith works
through charity. Therefore the love of charity is the form of faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As appears from what has been said above (FS, Q[1], A[3];
FS, Q[18], A[6]), voluntary acts take their species from their end which
is the will's object. Now that which gives a thing its species, is after
the manner of a form in natural things. Wherefore the form of any
voluntary act is, in a manner, the end to which that act is directed,
both because it takes its species therefrom, and because the mode of an
action should correspond proportionately to the end. Now it is evident
from what has been said (A[1]), that the act of faith is directed to the
object of the will, i.e. the good, as to its end: and this good which is
the end of faith, viz. the Divine Good, is the proper object of charity.
Therefore charity is called the form of faith in so far as the act of
faith is perfected and formed by charity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Charity is called the form of faith because it quickens the
act of faith. Now nothing hinders one act from being quickened by
different habits, so as to be reduced to various species in a certain
order, as stated above (FS, Q[18], AA[6],7; FS, Q[61], A[2]) when we were
treating of human acts in general.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: This objection is true of an intrinsic form. But it is not
thus that charity is the form of faith, but in the sense that it quickens
the act of faith, as explained above.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Even obedience, and hope likewise, and whatever other virtue might precede the act of faith, is quickened by charity, as we
shall show further on (Q[23], A[8]), and consequently charity is spoken
of as the form of faith.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether lifeless faith can become living, or living faith, lifeless?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that lifeless faith does not become living, or
living faith lifeless. For, according to 1 Cor. 13:10, "when that which
is perfect is come, that which is in part shall be done away." Now
lifeless faith is imperfect in comparison with living faith. Therefore
when living faith comes, lifeless faith is done away, so that they are
not one identical habit.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a dead thing does not become a living thing. Now
lifeless faith is dead, according to James 2:20: "Faith without works is
dead." Therefore lifeless faith cannot become living.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, God's grace, by its advent, has no less effect in a
believer than in an unbeliever. Now by coming to an unbeliever it causes
the habit of faith. Therefore when it comes to a believer, who hitherto
had the habit of lifeless faith, it causes another habit of faith in him.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, as Boethius says (In Categ. Arist. i), "accidents cannot
be altered." Now faith is an accident. Therefore the same faith cannot be
at one time living, and at another, lifeless.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, A gloss on the words, "Faith without works is dead"
(James 2:20) adds, "by which it lives once more." Therefore faith which
was lifeless and without form hitherto, becomes formed and living.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, There have been various opinions on this question. For
some [*William of Auxerre, Sum. Aur. III, iii, 15] have said that living
and lifeless faith are distinct habits, but that when living faith comes,
lifeless faith is done away, and that, in like manner, when a man sins
mortally after having living faith, a new habit of lifeless faith is
infused into him by God. But it seems unfitting that grace should deprive man of a gift of God by coming to him, and that a gift of God should be
infused into man, on account of a mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Body Para. 2/3

Consequently others [*Alexander of Hales, Sum. Theol. iii, 64] have said
that living and lifeless faith are indeed distinct habits, but that, all
the same, when living faith comes the habit of lifeless faith is not
taken away, and that it remains together with the habit of living faith
in the same subject. Yet again it seems unreasonable that the habit of
lifeless faith should remain inactive in a person having living faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] Body Para. 3/3

We must therefore hold differently that living and lifeless faith are
one and the same habit. The reason is that a habit is differentiated by
that which directly pertains to that habit. Now since faith is a
perfection of the intellect, that pertains directly to faith, which
pertains to the intellect. Again, what pertains to the will, does not
pertain directly to faith, so as to be able to differentiate the habit of
faith. But the distinction of living from lifeless faith is in respect of
something pertaining to the will, i.e. charity, and not in respect of
something pertaining to the intellect. Therefore living and lifeless
faith are not distinct habits.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The saying of the Apostle refers to those imperfect things
from which imperfection is inseparable, for then, when the perfect comes
the imperfect must needs be done away. Thus with the advent of clear
vision, faith is done away, because it is essentially "of the things that
appear not." When, however, imperfection is not inseparable from the
imperfect thing, the same identical thing which was imperfect becomes
perfect. Thus childhood is not essential to man and consequently the same
identical subject who was a child, becomes a man. Now lifelessness is not
essential to faith, but is accidental thereto as stated above. Therefore
lifeless faith itself becomes living.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: That which makes an animal live is inseparable from an
animal, because it is its substantial form, viz. the soul: consequently a
dead thing cannot become a living thing, and a living and a dead thing
differ specifically. On the other hand that which gives faith its form,
or makes it live, is not essential to faith. Hence there is no comparison.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 3: Grace causes faith not only when faith begins anew to be in
a man, but also as long as faith lasts. For it has been said above (FP,
Q[104], A[1]; FS, Q[109], A[9]) that God is always working man's
justification, even as the sun is always lighting up the air. Hence grace
is not less effective when it comes to a believer than when it comes to
an unbeliever: since it causes faith in both, in the former by confirming
and perfecting it, in the latter by creating it anew.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2

We might also reply that it is accidental, namely on account of the
disposition of the subject, that grace does not cause faith in one who
has it already: just as, on the other hand, a second mortal sin does not
take away grace from one who has already lost it through a previous
mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: When living faith becomes lifeless, faith is not changed,
but its subject, the soul, which at one time has faith without charity,
and at another time, with charity.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether faith is a virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that faith is not a virtue. For virtue is directed
to the good, since "it is virtue that makes its subject good," as the
Philosopher states (Ethic. ii, 6). But faith is directed to the true.
Therefore faith is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, infused virtue is more perfect than acquired virtue. Now
faith, on account of its imperfection, is not placed among the acquired
intellectual virtues, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. vi, 3). Much
less, therefore, can it be considered an infused virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, living and lifeless faith are the same species, as
stated above (A[4]). Now lifeless faith is not a virtue, since it is not
connected with the other virtues. Therefore neither is living faith a
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, the gratuitous graces and the fruits are distinct from
the virtues. But faith is numbered among the gratuitous graces (1 Cor.
12:9) and likewise among the fruits (Gal. 5:23). Therefore faith is not a
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Man is justified by the virtues, since "justice is all
virtue," as the Philosopher states (Ethic. v, 1). Now man is justified by
faith according to Rm. 5:1: "Being justified therefore by faith let us
have peace," etc. Therefore faith is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As shown above, it is by human virtue that human acts are
rendered good; hence, any habit that is always the principle of a good
act, may be called a human virtue. Such a habit is living faith. For
since to believe is an act of the intellect assenting to the truth at the
command of the will, two things are required that this act may be
perfect: one of which is that the intellect should infallibly tend to its
object, which is the true; while the other is that the will should be
infallibly directed to the last end, on account of which it assents to
the true: and both of these are to be found in the act of living faith.
For it belongs to the very essence of faith that the intellect should
ever tend to the true, since nothing false can be the object of faith, as
proved above (Q[1], A[3]): while the effect of charity, which is the form
of faith, is that the soul ever has its will directed to a good end.
Therefore living faith is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] Body Para. 2/2

On the other hand, lifeless faith is not a virtue, because, though the
act of lifeless faith is duly perfect on the part of the intellect, it
has not its due perfection as regards the will: just as if temperance be
in the concupiscible, without prudence being in the rational part,
temperance is not a virtue, as stated above (FS, Q[65], A[1]), because
the act of temperance requires both an act of reason, and an act of the
concupiscible faculty, even as the act of faith requires an act of the
will, and an act of the intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The truth is itself the good of the intellect, since it is
its perfection: and consequently faith has a relation to some good in so
far as it directs the intellect to the true. Furthermore, it has a
relation to the good considered as the object of the will, inasmuch as it
is formed by charity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The faith of which the Philosopher speaks is based on human
reasoning in a conclusion which does not follow, of necessity, from its
premisses; and which is subject to be false: hence such like faith is not
a virtue. On the other hand, the faith of which we are speaking is based
on the Divine Truth, which is infallible, and consequently its object
cannot be anything false; so that faith of this kind can be a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Living and lifeless faith do not differ specifically, as
though they belonged to different species. But they differ as perfect and
imperfect within the same species. Hence lifeless faith, being imperfect,
does not satisfy the conditions of a perfect virtue, for "virtue is a
kind of perfection" (Phys. vii, text. 18).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 4: Some say that faith which is numbered among the gratuitous
graces is lifeless faith. But this is said without reason, since the
gratuitous graces, which are mentioned in that passage, are not common to
all the members of the Church: wherefore the Apostle says: "There are
diversities of graces," and again, "To one is given" this grace and "to
another" that. Now lifeless faith is common to all members of the Church,
because its lifelessness is not part of its substance, if we consider it
as a gratuitous gift. We must, therefore, say that in that passage, faith
denotes a certain excellency of faith, for instance, "constancy in
faith," according to a gloss, or the "word of faith."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 2/2

Faith is numbered among the fruits, in so far as it gives a certain
pleasure in its act by reason of its certainty, wherefore the gloss on
the fifth chapter to the Galatians, where the fruits are enumerated,
explains faith as being "certainty about the unseen."


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether faith is one virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that faith is not one. For just as faith is a gift
of God according to Eph. 2:8, so also wisdom and knowledge are numbered
among God's gifts according to Is. 11:2. Now wisdom and knowledge differ
in this, that wisdom is about eternal things, and knowledge about
temporal things, as Augustine states (De Trin. xii, 14,15). Since, then,
faith is about eternal things, and also about some temporal things, it
seems that faith is not one virtue, but divided into several parts.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, confession is an act of faith, as stated above (Q[3],
A[1]). Now confession of faith is not one and the same for all: since what we confess as past, the fathers of old confessed as yet to come, as
appears from Is. 7:14: "Behold a virgin shall conceive." Therefore faith
is not one.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, faith is common to all believers in Christ. But one
accident cannot be in many subjects. Therefore all cannot have one faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Apostle says (Eph. 4:5): "One Lord, one faith."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, If we take faith as a habit, we can consider it in two
ways. First on the part of the object, and thus there is one faith.
Because the formal object of faith is the First Truth, by adhering to
which we believe whatever is contained in the faith. Secondly, on the
part of the subject, and thus faith is differentiated according as it is
in various subjects. Now it is evident that faith, just as any other
habit, takes its species from the formal aspect of its object, but is
individualized by its subject. Hence if we take faith for the habit
whereby we believe, it is one specifically, but differs numerically
according to its various subjects.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] Body Para. 2/2

If, on the other hand, we take faith for that which is believed, then,
again, there is one faith, since what is believed by all is one same
thing: for though the things believed, which all agree in believing, be
diverse from one another, yet they are all reduced to one.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Temporal matters which are proposed to be believed, do not
belong to the object of faith, except in relation to something eternal,
viz. the First Truth, as stated above (Q[1], A[1]). Hence there is one
faith of things both temporal and eternal. It is different with wisdom
and knowledge, which consider temporal and eternal matters under their
respective aspects.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: This difference of past and future arises, not from any
difference in the thing believed, but from the different relationships of
believers to the one thing believed, as also we have mentioned above (FS,
Q[103], A[4]; FS, Q[107], A[1], ad 1).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: This objection considers numerical diversity of faith.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether faith is the first of the virtues?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that faith is not the first of the virtues. For a
gloss on Lk. 12:4, "I say to you My friends," says that fortitude is the
foundation of faith. Now the foundation precedes that which is founded
thereon. Therefore faith is not the first of the virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a gloss on Ps. 36, "Be not emulous," says that hope
"leads on to faith." Now hope is a virtue, as we shall state further on
(Q[17], A[1]). Therefore faith is not the first of the virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, it was stated above (A[2]) that the intellect of the
believer is moved, out of obedience to God, to assent to matters of
faith. Now obedience also is a virtue. Therefore faith is not the first
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, not lifeless but living faith is the foundation, as a
gloss remarks on 1 Cor. 3:11 [*Augustine, De Fide et Oper. xvi.]. Now
faith is formed by charity, as stated above (A[3]). Therefore it is owing
to charity that faith is the foundation: so that charity is the
foundation yet more than faith is (for the foundation is the first part
of a building) and consequently it seems to precede faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, the order of habits is taken from the order of acts.
Now, in the act of faith, the act of the will which is perfected by
charity, precedes the act of the intellect, which is perfected by faith,
as the cause which precedes its effect. Therefore charity precedes faith.
Therefore faith is not the first of the virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Apostle says (Heb. 11:1) that "faith is the
substance of things to be hoped for." Now the substance of a thing is
that which comes first. Therefore faith is first among the virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, One thing can precede another in two ways: first, by its
very nature; secondly, by accident. Faith, by its very nature, precedes
all other virtues. For since the end is the principle in matters of
action, as stated above (FS, Q[13], A[3]; FS, Q[34], A[4], ad 1), the
theological virtues, the object of which is the last end, must needs
precede all the others. Again, the last end must of necessity be present
to the intellect before it is present to the will, since the will has no
inclination for anything except in so far as it is apprehended by the
intellect. Hence, as the last end is present in the will by hope and
charity, and in the intellect, by faith, the first of all the virtues
must, of necessity, be faith, because natural knowledge cannot reach God
as the object of heavenly bliss, which is the aspect under which hope and
charity tend towards Him.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Body Para. 2/3

On the other hand, some virtues can precede faith accidentally. For an
accidental cause precedes its effect accidentally. Now that which removes
an obstacle is a kind of accidental cause, according to the Philosopher
(Phys. viii, 4): and in this sense certain virtues may be said to precede
faith accidentally, in so far as they remove obstacles to belief. Thus
fortitude removes the inordinate fear that hinders faith; humility
removes pride, whereby a man refuses to submit himself to the truth of
faith. The same may be said of some other virtues, although there are no
real virtues, unless faith be presupposed, as Augustine states (Contra
Julian. iv, 3).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] Body Para. 3/3

This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Hope cannot lead to faith absolutely. For one cannot hope
to obtain eternal happiness, unless one believes this possible, since
hope does not tend to the impossible, as stated above (FS, Q[40], A[1]).
It is, however, possible for one to be led by hope to persevere in faith,
or to hold firmly to faith; and it is in this sense that hope is said to
lead to faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Obedience is twofold: for sometimes it denotes the
inclination of the will to fulfil God's commandments. In this way it is
not a special virtue, but is a general condition of every virtue; since
all acts of virtue come under the precepts of the Divine law, as stated
above (FS, Q[100], A[2]); and thus it is requisite for faith. In another
way, obedience denotes an inclination to fulfil the commandments
considered as a duty. In this way it is a special virtue, and a part of
justice: for a man does his duty by his superior when he obeys him: and
thus obedience follows faith, whereby man knows that God is his superior,
Whom he must obey.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: To be a foundation a thing requires not only to come first,
but also to be connected with the other parts of the building: since the
building would not be founded on it unless the other parts adhered to it.
Now the connecting bond of the spiritual edifice is charity, according to
Col. 3:14: "Above all . . . things have charity which is the bond of
perfection." Consequently faith without charity cannot be the foundation:
and yet it does not follow that charity precedes faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[7] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: Some act of the will is required before faith, but not an
act of the will quickened by charity. This latter act presupposes faith,
because the will cannot tend to God with perfect love, unless the
intellect possesses right faith about Him.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether faith is more certain than science and the other intellectual
virtues?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that faith is not more certain than science and the
other intellectual virtues. For doubt is opposed to certitude, wherefore
a thing would seem to be the more certain, through being less doubtful,
just as a thing is the whiter, the less it has of an admixture of black.
Now understanding, science and also wisdom are free of any doubt about
their objects; whereas the believer may sometimes suffer a movement of
doubt, and doubt about matters of faith. Therefore faith is no more
certain than the intellectual virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/2

OBJ 2: Further, sight is more certain than hearing. But "faith is
through hearing" according to Rm. 10:17; whereas understanding, science
and wisdom imply some kind of intellectual sight. Therefore science and
understanding are more certain than faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 2/2

Further, in matters concerning the intellect, the more perfect is the
more certain. Now understanding is more perfect than faith, since faith
is the way to understanding, according to another version [*The
Septuagint] of Is. 7:9: "If you will not believe, you shall not
understand [Vulg.: 'continue']": and Augustine says (De Trin. xiv, 1)
that "faith is strengthened by science." Therefore it seems that science
or understanding is more certain than faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Apostle says (1 Thess. 2:15): "When you had
received of us the word of the hearing," i.e. by faith . . . "you
received it not as the word of men, but, as it is indeed, the word of
God." Now nothing is more certain than the word of God. Therefore science
is not more certain than faith; nor is anything else.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[57], A[4], ad 2) two of the
intellectual virtues are about contingent matter, viz. prudence and art;
to which faith is preferable in point of certitude, by reason of its
matter, since it is about eternal things, which never change, whereas the
other three intellectual virtues, viz. wisdom, science [*In English the
corresponding 'gift' is called knowledge] and understanding, are about
necessary things, as stated above (FS, Q[57], A[5], ad 3). But it must be
observed that wisdom, science and understanding may be taken in two ways:
first, as intellectual virtues, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. vi,
2,3); secondly, for the gifts of the Holy Ghost. If we consider them in
the first way, we must note that certitude can be looked at in two ways.
First, on the part of its cause, and thus a thing which has a more
certain cause, is itself more certain. In this way faith is more certain
than those three virtues, because it is founded on the Divine truth,
whereas the aforesaid three virtues are based on human reason. Secondly,
certitude may be considered on the part of the subject, and thus the more
a man's intellect lays hold of a thing, the more certain it is. In this
way, faith is less certain, because matters of faith are above the human
intellect, whereas the objects of the aforesaid three virtues are not.
Since, however, a thing is judged simply with regard to its cause, but
relatively, with respect to a disposition on the part of the subject, it
follows that faith is more certain simply, while the others are more
certain relatively, i.e. for us. Likewise if these three be taken as
gifts received in this present life, they are related to faith as to
their principle which they presuppose: so that again, in this way, faith
is more certain.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: This doubt is not on the side of the cause of faith, but on
our side, in so far as we do not fully grasp matters of faith with our
intellect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Other things being equal sight is more certain than
hearing; but if (the authority of) the person from whom we hear greatly
surpasses that of the seer's sight, hearing is more certain than sight:
thus a man of little science is more certain about what he hears on the
authority of an expert in science, than about what is apparent to him
according to his own reason: and much more is a man certain about what he
hears from God, Who cannot be deceived, than about what he sees with his
own reason, which can be mistaken.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[4] A[8] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The gifts of understanding and knowledge are more perfect
than the knowledge of faith in the point of their greater clearness, but
not in regard to more certain adhesion: because the whole certitude of
the gifts of understanding and knowledge, arises from the certitude of
faith, even as the certitude of the knowledge of conclusions arises from
the certitude of premisses. But in so far as science, wisdom and
understanding are intellectual virtues, they are based upon the natural
light of reason, which falls short of the certitude of God's word, on
which faith is founded.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License