Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] Out. Para. 1/2 - OF SLOTH (FOUR ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] Out. Para. 1/2 - OF SLOTH (FOUR ARTICLES)

We must now consider the vices opposed to the joy of charity. This joy
is either about the Divine good, and then its contrary is sloth, or about
our neighbor's good, and then its contrary is envy. Wherefore we must
consider (1) Sloth and (2) Envy.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] Out. Para. 2/2

Under the first head there are four points of inquiry:

(1) Whether sloth is a sin?

(2) Whether it is a special vice?

(3) Whether it is a mortal sin?

(4) Whether it is a capital sin?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sloth is a sin?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that sloth is not a sin. For we are neither praised
nor blamed for our passions, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. ii, 5).
Now sloth is a passion, since it is a kind of sorrow, according to
Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 14), and as we stated above (FS, Q[35], A[8]
). Therefore sloth is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, no bodily failing that occurs at fixed times is a sin.
But sloth is like this, for Cassian says (De Instit. Monast. x, [*De
Institutione Caeobiorum]): "The monk is troubled with sloth chiefly about
the sixth hour: it is like an intermittent fever, and inflicts the soul
of the one it lays low with burning fires at regular and fixed
intervals." Therefore sloth is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, that which proceeds from a good root is, seemingly, no
sin. Now sloth proceeds from a good root, for Cassian says (De Instit.
Monast. x) that "sloth arises from the fact that we sigh at being
deprived of spiritual fruit, and think that other monasteries and those
which are a long way off are much better than the one we dwell in": all
of which seems to point to humility. Therefore sloth is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, all sin is to be avoided, according to Ecclus. 21:2:
"Flee from sins as from the face of a serpent." Now Cassian says (De
Instit. Monast. x): "Experience shows that the onslaught of sloth is not
to be evaded by flight but to be conquered by resistance." Therefore
sloth is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Whatever is forbidden in Holy Writ is a sin. Now such
is sloth [acedia]: for it is written (Ecclus. 6:26): "Bow down thy
shoulder, and bear her," namely spiritual wisdom, "and be not grieved
[acedieris] with her bands." Therefore sloth is a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, Sloth, according to Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 14) is
an oppressive sorrow, which, to wit, so weighs upon man's mind, that he
wants to do nothing; thus acid things are also cold. Hence sloth implies
a certain weariness of work, as appears from a gloss on Ps. 106:18,
"Their soul abhorred all manner of meat," and from the definition of some
who say that sloth is a "sluggishness of the mind which neglects to begin
good."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Body Para. 2/3

Now this sorrow is always evil, sometimes in itself, sometimes in its
effect. For sorrow is evil in itself when it is about that which is
apparently evil but good in reality, even as, on the other hand, pleasure
is evil if it is about that which seems to be good but is, in truth,
evil. Since, then, spiritual good is a good in very truth, sorrow about
spiritual good is evil in itself. And yet that sorrow also which is about
a real evil, is evil in its effect, if it so oppresses man as to draw him
away entirely from good deeds. Hence the Apostle (2 Cor. 2:7) did not
wish those who repented to be "swallowed up with overmuch sorrow."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] Body Para. 3/3

Accordingly, since sloth, as we understand it here, denotes sorrow for
spiritual good, it is evil on two counts, both in itself and in point of
its effect. Consequently it is a sin, for by sin we mean an evil movement
of the appetite, as appears from what has been said above (Q[10], A[2];
FS, Q[74], A[4]).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Passions are not sinful in themselves; but they are
blameworthy in so far as they are applied to something evil, just as they
deserve praise in so far as they are applied to something good. Wherefore
sorrow, in itself, calls neither for praise nor for blame: whereas
moderate sorrow for evil calls for praise, while sorrow for good, and
again immoderate sorrow for evil, call for blame. It is in this sense
that sloth is said to be a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The passions of the sensitive appetite may either be venial
sins in themselves, or incline the soul to mortal sin. And since the
sensitive appetite has a bodily organ, it follows that on account of some
bodily transmutation a man becomes apt to commit some particular sin.
Hence it may happen that certain sins may become more insistent, through
certain bodily transmutations occurring at certain fixed times. Now all
bodily effects, of themselves, dispose one to sorrow; and thus it is that
those who fast are harassed by sloth towards mid-day, when they begin to
feel the want of food, and to be parched by the sun's heat.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: It is a sign of humility if a man does not think too much
of himself, through observing his own faults; but if a man contemns the
good things he has received from God, this, far from being a proof of
humility, shows him to be ungrateful: and from such like contempt results
sloth, because we sorrow for things that we reckon evil and worthless.
Accordingly we ought to think much of the goods of others, in such a way
as not to disparage those we have received ourselves, because if we did
they would give us sorrow.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Sin is ever to be shunned, but the assaults of sin should
be overcome, sometimes by flight, sometimes by resistance; by flight when
a continued thought increases the incentive to sin, as in lust; for which
reason it is written (1 Cor. 6:18): "Fly fornication"; by resistance,
when perseverance in the thought diminishes the incentive to sin, which
incentive arises from some trivial consideration. This is the case with
sloth, because the more we think about spiritual goods, the more pleasing
they become to us, and forthwith sloth dies away.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sloth is a special vice?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that sloth is not a special vice. For that which is
common to all vices does not constitute a special kind of vice. But every
vice makes a man sorrowful about the opposite spiritual good: for the
lustful man is sorrowful about the good of continence, and the glutton
about the good of abstinence. Since then sloth is sorrow for spiritual
good, as stated above (A[1]), it seems that sloth is not a special sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, sloth, through being a kind of sorrow, is opposed to
joy. Now joy is not accounted one special virtue. Therefore sloth should
not be reckoned a special vice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, since spiritual good is a general kind of object, which
virtue seeks, and vice shuns, it does not constitute a special virtue or
vice, unless it be determined by some addition. Now nothing, seemingly,
except toil, can determine it to sloth, if this be a special vice;
because the reason why a man shuns spiritual goods, is that they are
toilsome, wherefore sloth is a kind of weariness: while dislike of toil,
and love of bodily repose seem to be due to the same cause, viz.
idleness. Hence sloth would be nothing but laziness, which seems untrue,
for idleness is opposed to carefulness, whereas sloth is opposed to joy.
Therefore sloth is not a special vice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Gregory (Moral. xxxi, 45) distinguishes sloth from the
other vices. Therefore it is a special vice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Since sloth is sorrow for spiritual good, if we take
spiritual good in a general way, sloth will not be a special vice,
because, as stated above (FS, Q[71], A[1]), every vice shuns the
spiritual good of its opposite virtue. Again it cannot be said that sloth
is a special vice, in so far as it shuns spiritual good, as toilsome, or
troublesome to the body, or as a hindrance to the body's pleasure, for
this again would not sever sloth from carnal vices, whereby a man seeks
bodily comfort and pleasure.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[2] Body Para. 2/2

Wherefore we must say that a certain order exists among spiritual goods,
since all the spiritual goods that are in the acts of each virtue are
directed to one spiritual good, which is the Divine good, about which
there is a special virtue, viz. charity. Hence it is proper to each
virtue to rejoice in its own spiritual good, which consists in its own
act, while it belongs specially to charity to have that spiritual joy
whereby one rejoices in the Divine good. In like manner the sorrow
whereby one is displeased at the spiritual good which is in each act of
virtue, belongs, not to any special vice, but to every vice, but sorrow
in the Divine good about which charity rejoices, belongs to a special
vice, which is called sloth. This suffices for the Replies to the
Objections.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sloth is a mortal sin?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that sloth is not a mortal sin. For every mortal
sin is contrary to a precept of the Divine Law. But sloth seems contrary
to no precept, as one may see by going through the precepts of the
Decalogue. Therefore sloth is not a mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, in the same genus, a sin of deed is no less grievous
than a sin of thought. Now it is not a mortal sin to refrain in deed from
some spiritual good which leads to God, else it would be a mortal sin not
to observe the counsels. Therefore it is not a mortal sin to refrain in
thought from such like spiritual works. Therefore sloth is not a mortal
sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, no mortal sin is to be found in a perfect man. But sloth
is to be found in a perfect man: for Cassian says (De Instit. Caenob. x,
l) that "sloth is well known to the solitary, and is a most vexatious and
persistent foe to the hermit." Therefore sloth is not always a mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (2 Cor. 7:20): "The sorrow of the world
worketh death." But such is sloth; for it is not sorrow "according to
God," which is contrasted with sorrow of the world. Therefore it is a
mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[88], AA[1],2), mortal sin is so
called because it destroys the spiritual life which is the effect of
charity, whereby God dwells in us. Wherefore any sin which by its very
nature is contrary to charity is a mortal sin by reason of its genus.
And such is sloth, because the proper effect of charity is joy in God, as
stated above (Q[28], A[1]), while sloth is sorrow about spiritual good in
as much as it is a Divine good. Therefore sloth is a mortal sin in
respect of its genus. But it must be observed with regard to all sins
that are mortal in respect of their genus, that they are not mortal, save
when they attain to their perfection. Because the consummation of sin is
in the consent of reason: for we are speaking now of human sins
consisting in human acts, the principle of which is the reason. Wherefore
if the sin be a mere beginning of sin in the sensuality alone, without
attaining to the consent of reason, it is a venial sin on account of the
imperfection of the act. Thus in the genus of adultery, the concupiscence
that goes no further than the sensuality is a venial sin, whereas if it
reach to the consent of reason, it is a mortal sin. So too, the movement
of sloth is sometimes in the sensuality alone, by reason of the
opposition of the flesh to the spirit, and then it is a venial sin;
whereas sometimes it reaches to the reason, which consents in the
dislike, horror and detestation of the Divine good, on account of the
flesh utterly prevailing over the spirit. In this case it is evident that
sloth is a mortal sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Sloth is opposed to the precept about hallowing the Sabbath
day. For this precept, in so far as it is a moral precept, implicitly
commands the mind to rest in God: and sorrow of the mind about the Divine
good is contrary thereto.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Sloth is not an aversion of the mind from any spiritual
good, but from the Divine good, to which the mind is obliged to adhere.
Wherefore if a man is sorry because someone forces him to do acts of
virtue that he is not bound to do, this is not a sin of sloth; but when
he is sorry to have to do something for God's sake.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Imperfect movements of sloth are to be found in holy men,
but they do not reach to the consent of reason.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sloth should be accounted a capital vice?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that sloth ought not to be accounted a capital
vice. For a capital vice is one that moves a man to sinful acts, as
stated above (Q[34], A[5]). Now sloth does not move one to action, but on
the contrary withdraws one from it. Therefore it should not be accounted
a capital sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a capital sin is one to which daughters are assigned.
Now Gregory (Moral. xxxi, 45) assigns six daughters to sloth, viz.
"malice, spite, faint-heartedness, despair, sluggishness in regard to the
commandments, wandering of the mind after unlawful things." Now these do
not seem in reality to arise from sloth. For "spite" is, seemingly the
same as hatred, which arises from envy, as stated above (Q[34], A[6]);
"malice" is a genus which contains all vices, and, in like manner, a
"wandering" of the mind after unlawful things is to be found in every
vice; "sluggishness" about the commandments seems to be the same as
sloth, while "faint-heartedness" and "despair" may arise from any sin.
Therefore sloth is not rightly accounted a capital sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, Isidore distinguishes the vice of sloth from the vice of
sorrow, saying (De Summo Bono ii, 37) that in so far as a man shirks his
duty because it is distasteful and burdensome, it is sorrow, and in so
far as he is inclined to undue repose, it is sloth: and of sorrow he says
that it gives rise to "spite, faint-heartedness, bitterness, despair,"
whereas he states that from sloth seven things arise, viz. "idleness,
drowsiness, uneasiness of the mind, restlessness of the body,
instability, loquacity, curiosity." Therefore it seems that either
Gregory or Isidore has wrongly assigned sloth as a capital sin together
with its daughters.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The same Gregory (Moral. xxxi, 45) states that sloth is
a capital sin, and has the daughters aforesaid.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[84], AA[3],4), a capital vice is
one which easily gives rise to others as being their final cause. Now
just as we do many things on account of pleasure, both in order to obtain
it, and through being moved to do something under the impulse of
pleasure, so again we do many things on account of sorrow, either that we
may avoid it, or through being exasperated into doing something under
pressure thereof. Wherefore, since sloth is a kind of sorrow, as stated
above (A[2]; FS, Q[85], A[8]), it is fittingly reckoned a capital sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Sloth by weighing on the mind, hinders us from doing things
that cause sorrow: nevertheless it induces the mind to do certain things,
either because they are in harmony with sorrow, such as weeping, or
because they are a means of avoiding sorrow.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Gregory fittingly assigns the daughters of sloth. For
since, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 5,6) "no man can be a
long time in company with what is painful and unpleasant," it follows
that something arises from sorrow in two ways: first, that man shuns
whatever causes sorrow; secondly, that he passes to other things that
give him pleasure: thus those who find no joy in spiritual pleasures,
have recourse to pleasures of the body, according to the Philosopher
(Ethic. x, 6). Now in the avoidance of sorrow the order observed is that
man at first flies from unpleasant objects, and secondly he even
struggles against such things as cause sorrow. Now spiritual goods which
are the object of the sorrow of sloth, are both end and means. Avoidance
of the end is the result of "despair," while avoidance of those goods
which are the means to the end, in matters of difficulty which come under
the counsels, is the effect of "faint-heartedness," and in matters of
common righteousness, is the effect of "sluggishness about the
commandments." The struggle against spiritual goods that cause sorrow is
sometimes with men who lead others to spiritual goods, and this is called
"spite"; and sometimes it extends to the spiritual goods themselves, when
a man goes so far as to detest them, and this is properly called
"malice." In so far as a man has recourse to eternal objects of pleasure,
the daughter of sloth is called "wandering after unlawful things." From
this it is clear how to reply to the objections against each of the
daughters: for "malice" does not denote here that which is generic to all
vices, but must be understood as explained. Nor is "spite" taken as
synonymous with hatred, but for a kind of indignation, as stated above:
and the same applies to the others.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[35] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: This distinction between sorrow and sloth is also given by
Cassian (De Instit. Caenob. x, 1). But Gregory more fittingly (Moral.
xxxi, 45) calls sloth a kind of sorrow, because, as stated above (A[2]),
sorrow is not a distinct vice, in so far as a man shirks a distasteful
and burdensome work, or sorrows on account of any other cause whatever,
but only in so far as he is sorry on account of the Divine good, which
sorrow belongs essentially to sloth; since sloth seeks undue rest in so
far as it spurns the Divine good. Moreover the things which Isidore
reckons to arise from sloth and sorrow, are reduced to those mentioned by
Gregory: for "bitterness" which Isidore states to be the result of
sorrow, is an effect of "spite." "Idleness" and "drowsiness" are reduced
to "sluggishness about the precepts": for some are idle and omit them
altogether, while others are drowsy and fulfil them with negligence. All
the other five which he reckons as effects of sloth, belong to the
"wandering of the mind after unlawful things." This tendency to wander,
if it reside in the mind itself that is desirous of rushing after various
things without rhyme or reason, is called "uneasiness of the mind," but
if it pertains to the imaginative power, it is called "curiosity"; if it
affect the speech it is called "loquacity"; and in so far as it affects a
body that changes place, it is called "restlessness of the body," when,
to wit, a man shows the unsteadiness of his mind, by the inordinate
movements of members of his body; while if it causes the body to move
from one place to another, it is called "instability"; or "instability"
may denote changeableness of purpose.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License