Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF INJUSTICE (FOUR ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF INJUSTICE (FOUR ARTICLES)

We must now consider injustice, under which head there are four points
of inquiry:

(1) Whether injustice is a special vice?

(2) Whether it is proper to the unjust man to do unjust deeds?

(3) Whether one can suffer injustice willingly?

(4) Whether injustice is a mortal sin according to its genus?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether injustice is a special virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that injustice is not a special vice. For it is
written (1 Jn. 3:4): "All sin is iniquity [*Vulg.: 'Whosoever committeth
sin, committeth also iniquity; and sin is iniquity']." Now iniquity would
seem to be the same as injustice, because justice is a kind of equality,
so that injustice is apparently the same as inequality or iniquity.
Therefore injustice is not a special sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, no special sin is contrary to all the virtues. But
injustice is contrary to all the virtues: for as regards adultery it is
opposed to chastity, as regards murder it is opposed to meekness, and in
like manner as regards the other sins. Therefore injustice is not a
special sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, injustice is opposed to justice which is in the will.
But every sin is in the will, as Augustine declares (De Duabus Anim. x).
Therefore injustice is not a special sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Injustice is contrary to justice. But justice is a
special virtue. Therefore injustice is a special vice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Injustice is twofold. First there is illegal injustice
which is opposed to legal justice: and this is essentially a special
vice, in so far as it regards a special object, namely the common good
which it contemns; and yet it is a general vice, as regards the
intention, since contempt of the common good may lead to all kinds of
sin. Thus too all vices, as being repugnant to the common good, have the
character of injustice, as though they arose from injustice, in accord
with what has been said above about justice (Q[58], AA[5],6). Secondly we
speak of injustice in reference to an inequality between one person and
another, when one man wishes to have more goods, riches for example, or
honors, and less evils, such as toil and losses, and thus injustice has a
special matter and is a particular vice opposed to particular justice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Even as legal justice is referred to human common good, so
Divine justice is referred to the Divine good, to which all sin is repugnant, and in this sense all sin is said to be iniquity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Even particular justice is indirectly opposed to all the
virtues; in so far, to wit, as even external acts pertain both to justice
and to the other moral virtues, although in different ways as stated
above (Q[58], A[9], ad 2).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The will, like the reason, extends to all moral matters,
i.e. passions and those external operations that relate to another
person. On the other hand justice perfects the will solely in the point
of its extending to operations that relate to another: and the same
applies to injustice.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a man is called unjust through doing an unjust thing?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that a man is called unjust through doing an unjust
thing. For habits are specified by their objects, as stated above (FS, Q[54], A[2]). Now the proper object of justice is the just, and the
proper object of injustice is the unjust. Therefore a man should be
called just through doing a just thing, and unjust through doing an
unjust thing.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher declares (Ethic. v, 9) that they hold a
false opinion who maintain that it is in a man's power to do suddenly an
unjust thing, and that a just man is no less capable of doing what is
unjust than an unjust man. But this opinion would not be false unless it
were proper to the unjust man to do what is unjust. Therefore a man is to
be deemed unjust from the fact that he does an unjust thing.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, every virtue bears the same relation to its proper act,
and the same applies to the contrary vices. But whoever does what is
intemperate, is said to be intemperate. Therefore whoever does an unjust
thing, is said to be unjust.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 6) that "a man may do
an unjust thing without being unjust."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Even as the object of justice is something equal in
external things, so too the object of injustice is something unequal,
through more or less being assigned to some person than is due to him. To
this object the habit of injustice is compared by means of its proper act
which is called an injustice. Accordingly it may happen in two ways that
a man who does an unjust thing, is not unjust: first, on account of a
lack of correspondence between the operation and its proper object. For
the operation takes its species and name from its direct and not from its
indirect object: and in things directed to an end the direct is that
which is intended, and the indirect is what is beside the intention.
Hence if a man do that which is unjust, without intending to do an unjust
thing, for instance if he do it through ignorance, being unaware that it
is unjust, properly speaking he does an unjust thing, not directly, but
only indirectly, and, as it were, doing materially that which is unjust:
hence such an operation is not called an injustice. Secondly, this may
happen on account of a lack of proportion between the operation and the
habit. For an injustice may sometimes arise from a passion, for instance,
anger or desire, and sometimes from choice, for instance when the
injustice itself is the direct object of one's complacency. In the latter
case properly speaking it arises from a habit, because whenever a man has
a habit, whatever befits that habit is, of itself, pleasant to him.
Accordingly, to do what is unjust intentionally and by choice is proper
to the unjust man, in which sense the unjust man is one who has the habit
of injustice: but a man may do what is unjust, unintentionally or through
passion, without having the habit of injustice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: A habit is specified by its object in its direct and formal
acceptation, not in its material and indirect acceptation.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: It is not easy for any man to do an unjust thing from
choice, as though it were pleasing for its own sake and not for the sake
of something else: this is proper to one who has the habit, as the
Philosopher declares (Ethic. v, 9).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The object of temperance is not something established
externally, as is the object of justice: the object of temperance, i.e.
the temperate thing, depends entirely on proportion to the man himself.
Consequently what is accidental and unintentional cannot be said to be
temperate either materially or formally. In like manner neither can it be
called intemperate: and in this respect there is dissimilarity between
justice and the other moral virtues; but as regards the proportion
between operation and habit, there is similarity in all respects.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether we can suffer injustice willingly?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that one can suffer injustice willingly. For
injustice is inequality, as stated above (A[2]). Now a man by injuring
himself, departs from equality, even as by injuring another. Therefore a
man can do an injustice to himself, even as to another. But whoever does
himself an injustice, does so involuntarily. Therefore a man can
voluntarily suffer injustice especially if it be inflicted by himself.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, no man is punished by the civil law, except for having
committed some injustice. Now suicides were formerly punished according
to the law of the state by being deprived of an honorable burial, as the
Philosopher declares (Ethic. v, 11). Therefore a man can do himself an
injustice, and consequently it may happen that a man suffers injustice
voluntarily.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, no man does an injustice save to one who suffers that
injustice. But it may happen that a man does an injustice to one who
wishes it, for instance if he sell him a thing for more than it is worth.
Therefore a man may happen to suffer an injustice voluntarily.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, To suffer an injustice and to do an injustice are
contraries. Now no man does an injustice against his will. Therefore on
the other hand no man suffers an injustice except against his will.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Action by its very nature proceeds from an agent, whereas
passion as such is from another: wherefore the same thing in the same
respect cannot be both agent and patient, as stated in Phys. iii, 1;
viii, 5. Now the proper principle of action in man is the will, wherefore
man does properly and essentially what he does voluntarily, and on the
other hand a man suffers properly what he suffers against his will, since
in so far as he is willing, he is a principle in himself, and so,
considered thus, he is active rather than passive. Accordingly we must
conclude that properly and strictly speaking no man can do an injustice
except voluntarily, nor suffer an injustice save involuntarily; but that
accidentally and materially so to speak, it is possible for that which is
unjust in itself either to be done involuntarily (as when a man does
anything unintentionally), or to be suffered voluntarily (as when a man
voluntarily gives to another more than he owes him).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: When one man gives voluntarily to another that which he
does not owe him, he causes neither injustice nor inequality. For a man's
ownership depends on his will, so there is no disproportion if he forfeit
something of his own free-will, either by his own or by another's action.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: An individual person may be considered in two ways. First,
with regard to himself; and thus, if he inflict an injury on himself, it
may come under the head of some other kind of sin, intemperance for
instance or imprudence, but not injustice; because injustice no less than
justice, is always referred to another person. Secondly, this or that man
may be considered as belonging to the State as part thereof, or as
belonging to God, as His creature and image; and thus a man who kills
himself, does an injury not indeed to himself, but to the State and to
God. Wherefore he is punished in accordance with both Divine and human
law, even as the Apostle declares in respect of the fornicator (1 Cor.
3:17): "If any man violate the temple of God, him shall God destroy."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Suffering is the effect of external action. Now in the
point of doing and suffering injustice, the material element is that
which is done externally, considered in itself, as stated above (A[2]),
and the formal and essential element is on the part of the will of agent
and patient, as stated above (A[2]). Accordingly we must reply that
injustice suffered by one man and injustice done by another man always
accompany one another, in the material sense. But if we speak in the
formal sense a man can do an injustice with the intention of doing an
injustice, and yet the other man does not suffer an injustice, because
he suffers voluntarily; and on the other hand a man can suffer an
injustice if he suffer an injustice against his will, while the man who
does the injury unknowingly, does an injustice, not formally but only
materially.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether whoever does an injustice sins mortally?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that not everyone who does an injustice sins
mortally. For venial sin is opposed to mortal sin. Now it is sometimes a
venial sin to do an injury: for the Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 8) in
reference to those who act unjustly: "Whatever they do not merely in
ignorance but through ignorance is a venial matter." Therefore not
everyone that does an injustice sins mortally.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, he who does an injustice in a small matter, departs but
slightly from the mean. Now this seems to be insignificant and should be
accounted among the least of evils, as the Philosopher declares (Ethic.
ii, 9). Therefore not everyone that does an injustice sins mortally.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, charity is the "mother of all the virtues" [*Peter
Lombard, Sent. iii, D. 23], and it is through being contrary thereto that
a sin is called mortal. But not all the sins contrary to the other
virtues are mortal. Therefore neither is it always a mortal sin to do an
injustice.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Whatever is contrary to the law of God is a mortal sin.
Now whoever does an injustice does that which is contrary to the law of
God, since it amounts either to theft, or to adultery, or to murder, or
to something of the kind, as will be shown further on (Q[64], seqq.).
Therefore whoever does an injustice sins mortally.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[12], A[5]), when we were treating
of the distinction of sins, a mortal sin is one that is contrary to
charity which gives life to the soul. Now every injury inflicted on
another person is of itself contrary to charity, which moves us to will
the good of another. And so since injustice always consists in an injury
inflicted on another person, it is evident that to do an injustice is a
mortal sin according to its genus.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: This saying of the Philosopher is to be understood as
referring to ignorance of fact, which he calls "ignorance of particular
circumstances" [*Ethic. iii, 1], and which deserves pardon, and not to
ignorance of the law which does not excuse: and he who does an injustice
through ignorance, does no injustice except accidentally, as stated above
(A[2])

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: He who does an injustice in small matters falls short of
the perfection on an unjust deed, in so far as what he does may be deemed
not altogether contrary to the will of the person who suffers therefrom:
for instance, if a man take an apple or some such thing from another
man, in which case it is probable that the latter is not hurt or
displeased.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[59] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The sins which are contrary to the other virtues are not
always hurtful to another person, but imply a disorder affecting human
passions; hence there is no comparison.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License