Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] Out. Para. 1/3 - OF RELIGION (EIGHT ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] Out. Para. 1/3 - OF RELIGION (EIGHT ARTICLES)

We must now consider each of the foregoing virtues, in so far as our
present scope demands. We shall consider (1) religion, (2) piety, (3)
observance, (4) gratitude, (5) revenge, (6) truth, (7) friendship, (8)
liberality, (9) {epieikeia}. Of the other virtues that have been
mentioned we have spoken partly in the treatise on charity, viz. of
concord and the like, and partly in this treatise on justice, for
instance, of right commutations and of innocence. of legislative justice
we spoke in the treatise on prudence.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] Out. Para. 2/3

Religion offers a threefold consideration: (1) Religion considered in
itself; (2) its acts; (3) the opposite vices.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] Out. Para. 3/3

Under the first head there are eight points of inquiry:

(1) Whether religion regards only our relation to God?

(2) Whether religion is a virtue?

(3) Whether religion is one virtue?

(4) Whether religion is a special virtue?

(5) Whether religion is a theological virtue?

(6) Whether religion should be preferred to the other moral virtues?

(7) Whether religion has any external actions?

(8) Whether religion is the same as holiness?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion directs man to God alone?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion does not direct man to God alone. It
is written (James 1:27): "Religion clean and undefiled before God and the
Father is this, to visit the fatherless and widows in their tribulation,
and to keep oneself unspotted from this world." Now "to visit the
fatherless and widows" indicates an order between oneself and one's
neighbor, and "to keep oneself unspotted from this world" belongs to the
order of a man within himself. Therefore religion does not imply order to
God alone.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei x, 1) that "since in
speaking Latin not only unlettered but even most cultured persons ere
wont to speak of religion as being exhibited, to our human kindred and
relations as also to those who are linked with us by any kind of tie,
that term does not escape ambiguity when it is a question of Divine
worship, so that we be able to say without hesitation that religion is
nothing else but the worship of God." Therefore religion signifies a
relation not only to God but also to our kindred.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, seemingly "latria" pertains to religion. Now "latria
signifies servitude," as Augustine states (De Civ. Dei x, 1). And we are
bound to serve not only God, but also our neighbor, according to Gal.
5:13, "By charity of the spirit serve one another." Therefore religion
includes a relation to one's neighbor also.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, worship belongs to religion. Now man is said to worship
not only God, but also his neighbor, according to the saying of Cato
[*Dionysius Cato, Breves Sententiae], "Worship thy parents." Therefore
religion directs us also to our neighbor, and not only to God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, all those who are in the state of grace are subject to
God. Yet not all who are in a state of grace are called religious, but
only those who bind themselves by certain vows and observances, and to
obedience to certain men. Therefore religion seemingly does not denote a
relation of subjection of man to God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Tully says (Rhet. ii, 53) that "religion consists in
offering service and ceremonial rites to a superior nature that men call
divine."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, as Isidore says (Etym. x), "according to Cicero, a man is
said to be religious from 'religio,' because he often ponders over, and,
as it were, reads again [relegit], the things which pertain to the
worship of God," so that religion would seem to take its name from
reading over those things which belong to Divine worship because we ought
frequently to ponder over such things in our hearts, according to Prov.
3:6, "In all thy ways think on Him." According to Augustine (De Civ. Dei
x, 3) it may also take its name from the fact that "we ought to seek God
again, whom we had lost by our neglect" [*St. Augustine plays on the
words 'reeligere,' i.e. to choose over again, and 'negligere,' to neglect
or despise.]. Or again, religion may be derived from "religare" [to bind
together], wherefore Augustine says (De Vera Relig. 55): "May religion
bind us to the one Almighty God." However, whether religion take its name
from frequent reading, or from a repeated choice of what has been lost
through negligence, or from being a bond, it denotes properly a relation
to God. For it is He to Whom we ought to be bound as to our unfailing
principle; to Whom also our choice should be resolutely directed as to
our last end; and Whom we lose when we neglect Him by sin, and should recover by believing in Him and confessing our faith.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Religion has two kinds of acts. Some are its proper and
immediate acts, which it elicits, and by which man is directed to God
alone, for instance, sacrifice, adoration and the like. But it has other
acts, which it produces through the medium of the virtues which it
commands, directing them to the honor of God, because the virtue which is
concerned with the end, commands the virtues which are concerned with the
means. Accordingly "to visit the fatherless and widows in their
tribulation" is an act of religion as commanding, and an act of mercy as
eliciting; and "to keep oneself unspotted from this world" is an act of
religion as commanding, but of temperance or of some similar virtue as
eliciting.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Religion is referred to those things one exhibits to one's
human kindred, if we take the term religion in a broad sense, but not if
we take it in its proper sense. Hence, shortly before the passage quoted,
Augustine says: "In a stricter sense religion seems to denote, not any
kind of worship, but the worship of God."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Since servant implies relation to a lord, wherever there is
a special kind of lordship there must needs be a special kind of service.
Now it is evident that lordship belongs to God in a special and singular
way, because He made all things, and has supreme dominion over all.
Consequently a special kind of service is due to Him, which is known as
"latria" in Greek; and therefore it belongs to religion.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: We are said to worship those whom we honor, and to
cultivate [*In the Latin the same word 'colere' stands for 'worship' and
'cultivate']: a man's memory or presence: we even speak of cultivating
things that are beneath us, thus a farmer [agricola] is one who
cultivates the land, and an inhabitant [incola] is one who cultivates the
place where he dwells. Since, however, special honor is due to God as the
first principle of all things, to Him also is due a special kind of
worship, which in Greek is {Eusebeia} or {Theosebeia}, as Augustine
states (De Civ. Dei x, 1).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: Although the name "religious" may be given to all in
general who worship God, yet in a special way religious are those who
consecrate their whole life to the Divine worship, by withdrawing from
human affairs. Thus also the term "contemplative" is applied, not to
those who contemplate, but to those who give up their whole lives to
contemplation. Such men subject themselves to man, not for man's sake but
for God's sake, according to the word of the Apostle (Gal. 4:14), "You .
. . received me as an angel of God, even as Christ Jesus."


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion is a virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion is not a virtue. Seemingly it belongs
to religion to pay reverence to God. But reverence is an act of fear
which is a gift, as stated above (Q[19], A[9]). Therefore religion is not
a virtue but a gift

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, every virtue is a free exercise of the will, wherefore
it is described as an "elective" or voluntary "habit" [*Ethic. ii, 6].
Now, as stated above (A[1], ad 3) "latria" belongs to religion, and
"latria" denotes a kind of servitude. Therefore religion is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, according to Ethic. ii, 1, aptitude for virtue is in us
by nature, wherefore things pertaining to virtue belong to the dictate of
natural reason. Now, it belongs to religion "to offer ceremonial worship
to the Godhead" [*Cf. A[1]], and ceremonial matters, as stated above (FS,
Q[99], A[3], ad 2; FS, Q[101]), do not belong to the dictate of natural
reason. Therefore religion is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is enumerated with the other virtues, as appears
from what has been said above (Q[80]).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (Q[58], A[3]; FS, Q[55], AA[3],4) "a
virtue is that which makes its possessor good, and his act good
likewise," wherefore we must needs say that every good act belongs to a
virtue. Now it is evident that to render anyone his due has the aspect of
good, since by rendering a person his due, one becomes suitably
proportioned to him, through being ordered to him in a becoming manner.
But order comes under the aspect of good, just as mode and species,
according to Augustine (De Nat. Boni iii). Since then it belongs to
religion to pay due honor to someone, namely, to God, it is evident that
religion is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: To pay reverence to God is an act of the gift of fear. Now
it belongs to religion to do certain things through reverence for God.
Hence it follows, not that religion is the same as the gift of fear, but
that it is referred thereto as to something more excellent; for the gifts
are more excellent than the moral virtues, as stated above (Q[9], A[1],
ad 3; FS, Q[68], A[8]).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Even a slave can voluntarily do his duty by his master, and
so "he makes a virtue of necessity" [*Jerome, Ep. liv, ad Furiam.], by
doing his duty voluntarily. In like manner, to render due service to God
may be an act of virtue, in so far as man does so voluntarily.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: It belongs to the dictate of natural reason that man should
do something through reverence for God. But that he should do this or
that determinate thing does not belong to the dictate of natural reason,
but is established by Divine or human law.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion is one virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion is not one virtue. Religion directs
us to God, as stated above (A[1]). Now in God there are three Persons;
and also many attributes, which differ at least logically from one
another. Now a logical difference in the object suffices for a difference
of virtue, as stated above (Q[50], A[2], ad 2). Therefore religion is
not one virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, of one virtue there is seemingly one act, since habits
are distinguished by their acts. Now there are many acts of religion, for
instance to worship, to serve, to vow, to pray, to sacrifice and many
such like. Therefore religion is not one virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, adoration belongs to religion. Now adoration is paid to
images under one aspect, and under another aspect to God Himself. Since,
then, a difference of aspect distinguishes virtues, it would seem that
religion is not one virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (Eph. 4:5): "One God [Vulg.: 'Lord'], one
faith." Now true religion professes faith in one God. Therefore religion
is one virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[54], A[2], ad 1), habits are
differentiated according to a different aspect of the object. Now it
belongs to religion to show reverence to one God under one aspect,
namely, as the first principle of the creation and government of things.
Wherefore He Himself says (Malach. 1:6): "If . . . I be a father, where
is My honor?" For it belongs to a father to beget and to govern.
Therefore it is evident that religion is one virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The three Divine Persons are the one principle of the
creation and government of things, wherefore they are served by one
religion. The different aspects of the attributes concur under the aspect
of first principle, because God produces all things, and governs them by
the wisdom, will and power of His goodness. Wherefore religion is one
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: By the one same act man both serves and worships God, for
worship regards the excellence of God, to Whom reverence is due: while
service regards the subjection of man who, by his condition, is under an
obligation of showing reverence to God. To these two belong all acts
ascribed to religion, because, by them all, man bears witness to the
Divine excellence and to his own subjection to God, either by offering
something to God, or by assuming something Divine.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The worship of religion is paid to images, not as
considered in themselves, nor as things, but as images leading us to God
incarnate. Now movement to an image as image does not stop at the image,
but goes on to the thing it represents. Hence neither "latria" nor the
virtue of religion is differentiated by the fact that religious worship
is paid to the images of Christ.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion is a special virtue, distinct from the others?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion is not a special virtue distinct from
the others. Augustine says (De Civ. Dei x, 6): "Any action whereby we
are united to God in holy fellowship, is a true sacrifice." But sacrifice
belongs to religion. Therefore every virtuous deed belongs to religion;
and consequently religion is not a special virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Apostle says (1 Cor. 10:31): "Do all to the glory of
God." Now it belongs to religion to do anything in reverence of God, as
stated above (A[1], ad 2; A[2]). Therefore religion is not a special
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the charity whereby we love God is not distinct from the
charity whereby we love our neighbor. But according to Ethic. viii, 8 "to
be honored is almost to be loved." Therefore the religion whereby we
honor God is not a special virtue distinct from observance, or "dulia,"
or piety whereby we honor our neighbor. Therefore religion is not a
special virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is reckoned a part of justice, distinct from the
other parts.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Since virtue is directed to the good, wherever there is a
special aspect of good, there must be a special virtue. Now the good to
which religion is directed, is to give due honor to God. Again, honor is
due to someone under the aspect of excellence: and to God a singular
excellence is competent, since He infinitely surpasses all things and
exceeds them in every way. Wherefore to Him is special honor due: even as
in human affairs we see that different honor is due to different personal
excellences, one kind of honor to a father, another to the king, and so
on. Hence it is evident that religion is a special virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Every virtuous deed is said to be a sacrifice, in so far as
it is done out of reverence of God. Hence this does not prove that
religion is a general virtue, but that it commands all other virtues, as
stated above (A[1], ad 1).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Every deed, in so far as it is done in God's honor, belongs
to religion, not as eliciting but as commanding: those belong to religion
as eliciting which pertain to the reverence of God by reason of their
specific character.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The object of love is the good, but the object of honor and
reverence is something excellent. Now God's goodness is communicated to
the creature, but the excellence of His goodness is not. Hence the
charity whereby God is loved is not distinct from the charity whereby our
neighbor is loved; whereas the religion whereby God is honored, is
distinct from the virtues whereby we honor our neighbor.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion is a theological virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion is a theological virtue. Augustine
says (Enchiridion iii) that "God is worshiped by faith, hope and
charity," which are theological virtues. Now it belongs to religion to
pay worship to God. Therefore religion is a theological virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a theological virtue is one that has God for its object.
Now religion has God for its object, since it directs us to God alone, as
stated above (A[1]). Therefore religion is a theological virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, every virtue is either theological, or intellectual, or
moral, as is clear from what has been said (FS, QQ[57],58,62). Now it is
evident that religion is not an intellectual virtue, because its
perfection does not depend on the consideration of truth: nor is it a
moral virtue, which consists properly in observing the mean between too
much and too little. for one cannot worship God too much, according to
Ecclus. 43:33, "Blessing the Lord, exalt Him as much as you can; for He
is above all praise." Therefore it remains that it is a theological
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is reckoned a part of justice which is a moral
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (A[4]) religion pays due worship to God.
Hence two things are to be considered in religion: first that which it
offers to God, viz. worship, and this is by way of matter and object in
religion; secondly, that to which something is offered, viz. God, to Whom
worship is paid. And yet the acts whereby God is worshiped do not reach
out to God himself, as when we believe God we reach out to Him by
believing; for which reason it was stated (Q[1], AA[1],2,4) that God is
the object of faith, not only because we believe in a God, but because we
believe God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] Body Para. 2/2

Now due worship is paid to God, in so far as certain acts whereby God is
worshiped, such as the offering of sacrifices and so forth, are done out
of reverence for God. Hence it is evident that God is related to religion
not as matter or object, but as end: and consequently religion is not a
theological virtue whose object is the last end, but a moral virtue which
is properly about things referred to the end.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The power or virtue whose action deals with an end, moves
by its command the power or virtue whose action deals with matters
directed to that end. Now the theological virtues, faith, hope and
charity have an act in reference to God as their proper object:
wherefore, by their command, they cause the act of religion, which
performs certain deeds directed to God: and so Augustine says that God is
worshiped by faith, hope and charity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Religion directs man to God not as its object but as its
end.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 3: Religion is neither a theological nor an intellectual, but
a moral virtue, since it is a part of justice, and observes a mean, not
in the passions, but in actions directed to God, by establishing a kind
of equality in them. And when I say "equality," I do not mean absolute
equality, because it is not possible to pay God as much as we owe Him, but equality in consideration of man's ability and God's acceptance.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2

And it is possible to have too much in matters pertaining to the Divine
worship, not as regards the circumstance of quantity, but as regards
other circumstances, as when Divine worship is paid to whom it is not
due, or when it is not due, or unduly in respect of some other
circumstance.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion should be preferred to the other moral virtues?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion should not be preferred to the other
moral virtues. The perfection of a moral virtue consists in its observing
the mean, as stated in Ethic. ii, 6. But religion fails to observe the
mean of justice, since it does not render an absolute equal to God.
Therefore religion is not more excellent than the other moral virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, what is offered by one man to another is the more
praiseworthy, according as the person it is offered to is in greater
need: wherefore it is written (Is. 57:7): "Deal thy bread to the hungry."
But God needs nothing that we can offer Him, according to Ps. 15:2, "I
have said: Thou art my God, for Thou hast no need of my goods." Therefore
religion would seem less praiseworthy than the other virtues whereby
man's needs are relieved.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the greater. the obligation to do a thing, the less
praise does it deserve, according to 1 Cor. 9:16, "If I preach the
Gospel, it is no glory to me: a necessity lieth upon me." Now the more a
thing is due, the greater the obligation of paying it. Since, then, what
is paid to God by man is in the highest degree due to Him, it would seem
that religion is less praiseworthy than the other human virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The precepts pertaining to religion are given
precedence (Ex. 20) as being of greatest importance. Now the order of
precepts is proportionate to the order of virtues, since the precepts of
the Law prescribe acts of virtue. Therefore religion is the chief of the
moral virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Whatever is directed to an end takes its goodness from
being ordered to that end; so that the nearer it is to the end the better
it is. Now moral virtues, as stated above (A[5]; Q[4], A[7]), are about
matters that are ordered to God as their end. And religion approaches
nearer to God than the other moral virtues, in so far as its actions are
directly and immediately ordered to the honor of God. Hence religion
excels among the moral virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Virtue is praised because of the will, not because of the
ability: and therefore if a man fall short of equality which is the mean
of justice, through lack of ability, his virtue deserves no less praise,
provided there be no failing on the part of his will.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: In offering a thing to a man on account of its usefulness
to him, the more needy the man the more praiseworthy the offering,
because it is more useful: whereas we offer a thing to God not on account
of its usefulness to Him, but for the sake of His glory, and on account
of its usefulness to us.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Where there is an obligation to do a thing it loses the
luster of supererogation, but not the merit of virtue, provided it be
done voluntarily. Hence the argument proves nothing.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion has an external act?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion has not an external act. It is
written (Jn. 4:24): "God is a spirit, and they that adore Him, must adore
Him in spirit and in truth." Now external acts pertain, not to the spirit
but to the body. Therefore religion, to which adoration belongs, has acts
that are not external but internal.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the end of religion is to pay God reverence and honor.
Now it would savor of irreverence towards a superior, if one were to
offer him that which properly belongs to his inferior. Since then
whatever man offers by bodily actions, seems to be directed properly to
the relief of human needs, or to the reverence of inferior creatures, it
would seem unbecoming to employ them in showing reverence to God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, Augustine (De Civ. Dei vi, 10) commends Seneca for
finding fault with those who offered to idols those things that are wont
to be offered to men, because, to wit, that which befits mortals is
unbecoming to immortals. But such things are much less becoming to the
true God, Who is "exalted above all gods" [*Ps. 94:3]. Therefore it would
seem wrong to worship God with bodily actions. Therefore religion has no
bodily actions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (Ps. 83:3): "My heart and my flesh have
rejoiced in the living God." Now just as internal actions belong to the
heart, so do external actions belong to the members of the flesh.
Therefore it seems that God ought to be worshiped not only by internal
but also by external actions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, We pay God honor and reverence, not for His sake (because
He is of Himself full of glory to which no creature can add anything),
but for our own sake, because by the very fact that we revere and honor
God, our mind is subjected to Him; wherein its perfection consists, since
a thing is perfected by being subjected to its superior, for instance the
body is perfected by being quickened by the soul, and the air by being
enlightened by the sun. Now the human mind, in order to be united to God,
needs to be guided by the sensible world, since "invisible things . . .
are clearly seen, being understood by the things that are made," as the
Apostle says (Rm. 1:20). Wherefore in the Divine worship it is necessary
to make use of corporeal things, that man's mind may be aroused thereby,
as by signs, to the spiritual acts by means of which he is united to God.
Therefore the internal acts of religion take precedence of the others and
belong to religion essentially, while its external acts are secondary,
and subordinate to the internal acts.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Our Lord is speaking of that which is most important and
directly intended in the worship of God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: These external things are offered to God, not as though He
stood in need of them, according to Ps. 49:13, "Shall I eat the flesh of
bullocks? or shall I drink the blood of goats?" but as signs of the
internal and spiritual works, which are of themselves acceptable to God.
Hence Augustine says (De Civ. Dei x, 5): "The visible sacrifice is the
sacrament or sacred sign of the invisible sacrifice."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Idolaters are ridiculed for offering to idols things
pertaining to men, not as signs arousing them to certain spiritual
things, but as though they were of themselves acceptable to the idols;
and still more because they were foolish and wicked.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religion is the same as sanctity?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religion is not the same as sanctity. Religion
is a special virtue, as stated above (A[4]): whereas sanctity is a
general virtue, because it makes us faithful, and fulfil our just
obligations to God, according to Andronicus [*De Affectibus]. Therefore
sanctity is not the same as religion.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, sanctity seems to denote a kind of purity. For Dionysius
says (Div. Nom. xii) that "sanctity is free from all uncleanness, and is
perfect and altogether unspotted purity." Now purity would seem above all
to pertain to temperance which repels bodily uncleanness. Since then
religion belongs to justice, it would seem that sanctity is not the same
as religion.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, things that are opposite members of a division are not
identified with one another. But in an enumeration given above (Q[80], ad
4) of the parts of justice, sanctity is reckoned as distinct from
religion. Therefore sanctity is not the same as religion.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (Lk. 1:74,75): "That . . . we may serve
Him . . . in holiness and justice." Now, "to serve God" belongs to
religion, as stated above (A[1], ad 3; A[3], ad 2). Therefore religion is
the same as sanctity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, The word "sanctity" seems to have two significations. In
one way it denotes purity; and this signification fits in with the Greek,
for {hagios} means "unsoiled." In another way it denotes firmness,
wherefore in olden times the term "sancta" was applied to such things as
were upheld by law and were not to be violated. Hence a thing is said to
be sacred [sancitum] when it is ratified by law. Again, in Latin, this
word "sanctus" may be connected with purity, if it be resolved into
"sanguine tinctus, since, in olden times, those who wished to be purified
were sprinkled with the victim's blood," according to Isidore (Etym. x).
In either case the signification requires sanctity to be ascribed to
those things that are applied to the Divine worship; so that not only
men, but also the temple, vessels and such like things are said to be
sanctified through being applied to the worship of God. For purity is
necessary in order that the mind be applied to God, since the human mind
is soiled by contact with inferior things, even as all things depreciate
by admixture with baser things, for instance, silver by being mixed with
lead. Now in order for the mind to be united to the Supreme Being it must
be withdrawn from inferior things: and hence it is that without purity
the mind cannot be applied to God. Wherefore it is written (Heb. 12:14):
"Follow peace with all men, and holiness, without which no man shall see
God." Again, firmness is required for the mind to be applied to God, for
it is applied to Him as its last end and first beginning, and such things
must needs be most immovable. Hence the Apostle said (Rm. 8:38,39): "I am
sure that neither death, nor life . . . shall separate me [*Vulg.: 'shall
be able to separate us'] from the love of God."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] Body Para. 2/2

Accordingly, it is by sanctity that the human mind applies itself and
its acts to God: so that it differs from religion not essentially but
only logically. For it takes the name of religion according as it gives
God due service in matters pertaining specially to the Divine worship,
such as sacrifices, oblations, and so forth; while it is called sanctity,
according as man refers to God not only these but also the works of the
other virtues, or according as man by means of certain good works
disposes himself to the worship of God

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Sanctity is a special virtue according to its essence; and
in this respect it is in a way identified with religion. But it has a
certain generality, in so far as by its command it directs the acts of
all the virtues to the Divine good, even as legal justice is said to be a
general virtue, in so far as it directs the acts of all the virtues to
the common good.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Temperance practices purity, yet not so as to have the
character of sanctity unless it be referred to God. Hence of virginity
itself Augustine says (De Virgin. viii) that "it is honored not for what
it is, but for being consecrated to God."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[81] A[8] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Sanctity differs from religion as explained above, not
really but logically.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License