Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF PRODIGALITY (THREE ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF PRODIGALITY (THREE ARTICLES)

We must now consider prodigality, under which head there are three
points of inquiry:

(1) Whether prodigality is opposite to covetousness?

(2) Whether prodigality is a sin?

(3) Whether it is a graver sin that covetousness?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether prodigality is opposite to covetousness?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that prodigality is not opposite to covetousness. For
opposites cannot be together in the same subject. But some are at the
same time prodigal and covetous. Therefore prodigality is not opposite to
covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, opposites relate to one same thing. But covetousness, as
opposed to liberality, relates to certain passions whereby man is
affected towards money: whereas prodigality does not seem to relate to
any passions of the soul, since it is not affected towards money, or to
anything else of the kind. Therefore prodigality is not opposite to
covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, sin takes its species chiefly from its end, as stated
above (FS, Q[62], A[3]). Now prodigality seems always to be directed to
some unlawful end, for the sake of which the prodigal squanders his
goods. Especially is it directed to pleasures, wherefore it is stated
(Lk. 15:13) of the prodigal son that he "wasted his substance living
riotously." Therefore it seems that prodigality is opposed to temperance
and insensibility rather than to covetousness and liberality.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 7; iv, 1) that
prodigality is opposed to liberality, and illiberality, to which we give
here the name of covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, In morals vices are opposed to one another and to virtue
in respect of excess and deficiency. Now covetousness and prodigality
differ variously in respect of excess and deficiency. Thus, as regards
affection for riches, the covetous man exceeds by loving them more than
he ought, while the prodigal is deficient, by being less careful of them
than he ought: and as regards external action, prodigality implies excess
in giving, but deficiency in retaining and acquiring, while covetousness,
on the contrary, denotes deficiency in giving, but excess in acquiring
and retaining. Hence it is evident that prodigality is opposed to
covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Nothing prevents opposites from being in the same subject
in different respects. For a thing is denominated more from what is in it
principally. Now just as in liberality, which observes the mean, the
principal thing is giving, to which receiving and retaining are
subordinate, so, too, covetousness and prodigality regard principally
giving. Wherefore he who exceeds in giving is said to be "prodigal,"
while he who is deficient in giving is said to be "covetous." Now it
happens sometimes that a man is deficient in giving, without exceeding in
receiving, as the Philosopher observes (Ethic. iv, 1). And in like manner
it happens sometimes that a man exceeds in giving, and therefore is
prodigal, and yet at the same time exceeds in receiving. This may be due
either to some kind of necessity, since while exceeding in giving he is
lacking in goods of his own, so that he is driven to acquire unduly, and
this pertains to covetousness; or it may be due to inordinateness of the
mind, for he gives not for a good purpose, but, as though despising
virtue, cares not whence or how he receives. Wherefore he is prodigal and
covetous in different respects.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Prodigality regards passions in respect of money, not as
exceeding, but as deficient in them.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The prodigal does not always exceed in giving for the sake
of pleasures which are the matter of temperance, but sometimes through
being so disposed as not to care about riches, and sometimes on account
of something else. More frequently, however, he inclines to intemperance,
both because through spending too much on other things he becomes
fearless of spending on objects of pleasure, to which the concupiscence
of the flesh is more prone; and because through taking no pleasure in
virtuous goods, he seeks for himself pleasures of the body. Hence the
Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 1) "that many a prodigal ends in becoming
intemperate."


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether prodigality is a sin?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that prodigality is not a sin. For the Apostle says (1
Tim. 6:10): "Covetousness [Douay: 'desire of money'] is the root of all
evils." But it is not the root of prodigality, since this is opposed to
it. Therefore prodigality is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Apostle says (1 Tim. 6:17,18): "Charge the rich of
this world . . . to give easily, to communicate to others." Now this is
especially what prodigal persons do. Therefore prodigality is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, it belongs to prodigality to exceed in giving and to be
deficient in solicitude about riches. But this is most becoming to the
perfect, who fulfil the words of Our Lord (Mt. 6:34), "Be not . . .
solicitous for tomorrow," and (Mt. 19:21), "Sell all [Vulg.: 'what'] thou
hast, and give to the poor." Therefore prodigality is not a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The prodigal son is held to blame for his prodigality.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (A[1]), the opposition between
prodigality and covetousness is one of excess and deficiency; either of
which destroys the mean of virtue. Now a thing is vicious and sinful
through corrupting the good of virtue. Hence it follows that prodigality
is a sin.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Some expound this saying of the Apostle as referring, not
to actual covetousness, but to a kind of habitual covetousness, which is
the concupiscence of the "fomes" [*Cf. FS, Q[81], A[3], ad 2], whence
all sins arise. Others say that he is speaking of a general covetousness
with regard to any kind of good: and in this sense also it is evident
that prodigality arises from covetousness; since the prodigal seeks to
acquire some temporal good inordinately, namely, to give pleasure to
others, or at least to satisfy his own will in giving. But to one that
reviews the passage correctly, it is evident that the Apostle is speaking
literally of the desire of riches, for he had said previously (1 Tim.
6:9): "They that will become rich," etc. In this sense covetousness is
said to be "the root of all evils," not that all evils always arise from
covetousness, but because there is no evil that does not at some time
arise from covetousness. Wherefore prodigality sometimes is born of
covetousness, as when a man is prodigal in going to great expense in
order to curry favor with certain persons from whom he may receive riches.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The Apostle bids the rich to be ready to give and
communicate their riches, according as they ought. The prodigal does not
do this: since, as the Philosopher remarks (Ethic. iv, 1), "his giving is
neither good, nor for a good end, nor according as it ought to be. For
sometimes they give much to those who ought to be poor, namely, to
buffoons and flatterers, whereas to the good they give nothing."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The excess in prodigality consists chiefly, not in the
total amount given, but in the amount over and above what ought to be
given. Hence sometimes the liberal man gives more than the prodigal man,
if it be necessary. Accordingly we must reply that those who give all
their possessions with the intention of following Christ, and banish from
their minds all solicitude for temporal things, are not prodigal but
perfectly liberal.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether prodigality is a more grievous sin than covetousness?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that prodigality is a more grievous sin than
covetousness. For by covetousness a man injures his neighbor by not
communicating his goods to him, whereas by prodigality a man injures
himself, because the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 1) that "the wasting of
riches, which are the means whereby a man lives, is an undoing of his
very being." Now he that injures himself sins more grievously, according
to Ecclus. 14:5, "He that is evil to himself, to whom will he be good?"
Therefore prodigality is a more grievous sin than covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, a disorder that is accompanied by a laudable
circumstance is less sinful. Now the disorder of covetousness is
sometimes accompanied by a laudable circumstance, as in the case of those
who are unwilling to spend their own, lest they be driven to accept from
others: whereas the disorder of prodigality is accompanied by a
circumstance that calls for blame, inasmuch as we ascribe prodigality to
those who are intemperate, as the Philosopher observes (Ethic. iv, 1).
Therefore prodigality is a more grievous sin than covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, prudence is chief among the moral virtues, as stated
above (Q[56], A[1], ad 1; FS, Q[61], A[2], ad 1). Now prodigality is more
opposed to prudence than covetousness is: for it is written (Prov.
21:20): "There is a treasure to be desired, and oil in the dwelling of
the just; and the foolish man shall spend it": and the Philosopher says
(Ethic. iv, 6) that "it is the mark of a fool to give too much and
receive nothing." Therefore prodigality is a more grievous sin than
covetousness.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 6) that "the prodigal
seems to be much better than the illiberal man."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Prodigality considered in itself is a less grievous sin
than covetousness, and this for three reasons. First, because
covetousness differs more from the opposite virtue: since giving, wherein
the prodigal exceeds, belongs to liberality more than receiving or
retaining, wherein the covetous man exceeds. Secondly, because the
prodigal man is of use to the many to whom he gives, while the covetous
man is of use to no one, not even to himself, as stated in Ethic. iv, 6.
Thirdly, because prodigality is easily cured. For not only is the
prodigal on the way to old age, which is opposed to prodigality, but he
is easily reduced to a state of want, since much useless spending
impoverishes him and makes him unable to exceed in giving. Moreover,
prodigality is easily turned into virtue on account of its likeness
thereto. On the other hand, the covetous man is not easily cured, for the
reason given above (Q[118], A[5], ad 3).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The difference between the prodigal and the covetous man is
not that the former sins against himself and the latter against another.
For the prodigal sins against himself by spending that which is his, and
his means of support, and against others by spending the wherewithal to
help others. This applies chiefly to the clergy, who are the dispensers
of the Church's goods, that belong to the poor whom they defraud by their
prodigal expenditure. In like manner the covetous man sins against
others, by being deficient in giving; and he sins against himself,
through deficiency in spending: wherefore it is written (Eccles. 6:2): "A
man to whom God hath given riches . . . yet doth not give him the power
to eat thereof." Nevertheless the prodigal man exceeds in this, that he
injures both himself and others yet so as to profit some; whereas the
covetous man profits neither others nor himself, since he does not even
use his own goods for his own profit.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: In speaking of vices in general, we judge of them according
to their respective natures: thus, with regard to prodigality we note
that it consumes riches to excess, and with regard to covetousness that
it retains them to excess. That one spend too much for the sake of
intemperance points already to several additional sins, wherefore the
prodigal of this kind is worse, as stated in Ethic. iv, 1. That an
illiberal or covetous man refrain from taking what belongs to others,
although this appears in itself to call for praise, yet on account of the
motive for which he does so it calls for blame, since he is unwilling to
accept from others lest he be forced to give to others.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[119] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: All vices are opposed to prudence, even as all virtues are
directed by prudence: wherefore if a vice be opposed to prudence alone,
for this very reason it is deemed less grievous.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License