Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF PATIENCE (FIVE ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF PATIENCE (FIVE ARTICLES)

We must now consider patience. Under this head there are five points of
inquiry:

(1) Whether patience is a virtue?

(2) Whether it is the greatest of the virtues?

(3) Whether it can be had without grace?

(4) Whether it is a part of fortitude?

(5) Whether it is the same as longanimity?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether patience is a virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that patience is not a virtue. For the virtues are most
perfect in heaven, as Augustine says (De Trin. xiv). Yet patience is not
there, since no evils have to be borne there, according to Is. 49:10 and
Apoc. 7:16, "They shall not hunger nor thirst, neither shall the heat nor
the sun strike them." Therefore patience is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, no virtue can be found in the wicked, since virtue it is
"that makes its possessor good." Yet patience is sometimes found in
wicked men; for instance, in the covetous, who bear many evils patiently
that they may amass money, according to Eccles. 5:16, "All the days of
his life he eateth in darkness, and in many cares, and in misery and in
sorrow." Therefore patience is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the fruits differ from the virtues, as stated above (FS,
Q[70], A[1], ad 3). But patience is reckoned among the fruits (Gal.
5:22). Therefore patience is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (De Patientia i): "The virtue of the
soul that is called patience, is so great a gift of God, that we even
preach the patience of Him who bestows it upon us."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (Q[123], A[1]), the moral virtues are
directed to the good, inasmuch as they safeguard the good of reason
against the impulse of the passions. Now among the passions sorrow is
strong to hinder the good of reason, according to 2 Cor. 7:10, "The
sorrow of the world worketh death," and Ecclus. 30:25, "Sadness hath
killed many, and there is no profit in it." Hence the necessity for a
virtue to safeguard the good of reason against sorrow, lest reason give way to sorrow: and this patience does. Wherefore Augustine says (De
Patientia ii): "A man's patience it is whereby he bears evil with an
equal mind," i.e. without being disturbed by sorrow, "lest he abandon
with an unequal mind the goods whereby he may advance to better things."
It is therefore evident that patience is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The moral virtues do not remain in heaven as regards the
same act that they have on the way, in relation, namely, to the goods of
the present life, which will not remain in heaven: but they will remain
in their relation to the end, which will be in heaven. Thus justice will
not be in heaven in relation to buying and selling and other matters
pertaining to the present life, but it will remain in the point of being
subject to God. In like manner the act of patience, in heaven, will not
consist in bearing things, but in enjoying the goods to which we had
aspired by suffering. Hence Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiv) that
"patience itself will not be in heaven, since there is no need for it
except where evils have to be borne: yet that which we shall obtain by
patience will be eternal."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: As Augustine says (De Patientia ii; v) "properly speaking
those are patient who would rather bear evils without inflicting them,
than inflict them without bearing them. As for those who bear evils that
they may inflict evil, their patience is neither marvelous nor
praiseworthy, for it is no patience at all: we may marvel at their
hardness of heart, but we must refuse to call them patient."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: As stated above (FS, Q[11], A[1]), the very notion of fruit
denotes pleasure. And works of virtue afford pleasure in themselves, as
stated in Ethic. i, 8. Now the names of the virtues are wont to be
applied to their acts. Wherefore patience as a habit is a virtue. but as
to the pleasure which its act affords, it is reckoned a fruit, especially
in this, that patience safeguards the mind from being overcome by sorrow.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether patience is the greatest of the virtues?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that patience is the greatest of the virtues. For in
every genus that which is perfect is the greatest. Now "patience hath a
perfect work" (James 1:4). Therefore patience is the greatest of the
virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, all the virtues are directed to the good of the soul.
Now this seems to belong chiefly to patience; for it is written (Lk.
21:19): "In your patience you shall possess your souls." Therefore
patience is the greatest of the virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, seemingly that which is the safeguard and cause of other
things is greater than they are. But according to Gregory (Hom. xxxv in
Evang.) "patience is the root and safeguard of all the virtues."
Therefore patience is the greatest of the virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is not reckoned among the four virtues which Gregory
(Moral. xxii) and Augustine (De Morib. Eccl. xv) call principal.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Virtues by their very nature are directed to good. For it
is virtue that "makes its possessor good, and renders the latter's work
good" (Ethic. ii, 6). Hence it follows that a virtue's superiority and
preponderance over other virtues is the greater according as it inclines
man to good more effectively and directly. Now those virtues which are
effective of good, incline a man more directly to good than those which
are a check on the things which lead man away from good: and just as
among those that are effective of good, the greater is that which
establishes man in a greater good (thus faith, hope, and charity /are
greater than prudence and justice); so too among those that are a check
on things that withdraw man from good, the greater virtue is the one
which is a check on a greater obstacle to good. But dangers of death,
about which is fortitude, and pleasures of touch, with which temperance
is concerned, withdraw man from good more than any kind of hardship,
which is the object of patience. Therefore patience is not the greatest
of the virtues, but falls short, not only of the theological virtues, and
of prudence and justice which directly establish man in good, but also of
fortitude and temperance which withdraw him from greater obstacles to
good.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 1: Patience is said to have a perfect work in bearing
hardships: for these give rise first to sorrow, which is moderated by
patience; secondly, to anger, which is moderated by meekness; thirdly, to
hatred, which charity removes; fourthly, to unjust injury, which justice
forbids. Now that which removes the principle is the most perfect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2

Yet it does not follow, if patience be more perfect in this respect,
that it is more perfect simply.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Possession denotes undisturbed ownership; wherefore man is
said to possess his soul by patience, in so far as it removes by the root
the passions that are evoked by hardships and disturb the soul.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Patience is said to be the root and safeguard of all the
virtues, not as though it caused and preserved them directly, but merely
because it removes their obstacles.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether it is possible to have patience without grace?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that it is possible to have patience without grace. For
the more his reason inclines to a thing, the more is it possible for the
rational creature to accomplish it. Now it is more reasonable to suffer
evil for the sake of good than for the sake of evil. Yet some suffer evil
for evil's sake, by their own virtue and without the help of grace; for
Augustine says (De Patientia iii) that "men endure many toils and sorrows
for the sake of the things they love sinfully." Much more, therefore, is
it possible for man, without the help of grace, to bear evil for the sake
of good, and this is to be truly patient.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, some who are not in a state of grace have more
abhorrence for sinful evils than for bodily evils: hence some heathens
are related to have endured many hardships rather than betray their
country or commit some other misdeed. Now this is to be truly patient.
Therefore it seems that it is possible to have patience without the help
of grace.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, it is quite evident that some go through much trouble
and pain in order to regain health of the body. Now the health of the
soul is not less desirable than bodily health. Therefore in like manner
one may, without the help of grace, endure many evils for the health of
the soul, and this is to be truly patient.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (Ps. 61:6): "From Him," i.e. from God,
"is my patience."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As Augustine says (De Patientia iv), "the strength of
desire helps a man to bear toil and pain: and no one willingly undertakes
to bear what is painful, save for the sake of that which gives pleasure."
The reason of this is because sorrow and pain are of themselves
displeasing to the soul, wherefore it would never choose to suffer them
for their own sake, but only for the sake of an end. Hence it follows
that the good for the sake of which one is willing to endure evils, is
more desired and loved than the good the privation of which causes the
sorrow that we bear patiently. Now the fact that a man prefers the good
of grace to all natural goods, the loss of which may cause sorrow, is to
be referred to charity, which loves God above all things. Hence it is
evident that patience, as a virtue, is caused by charity, according to 1
Cor. 13:4, "Charity is patient."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

But it is manifest that it is impossible to have charity save through
grace, according to Rm. 5:5, "The charity of God is poured forth in our
hearts by the Holy Ghost Who is given to us." Therefore it is clearly
impossible to have patience without the help of grace.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The inclination of reason would prevail in human nature in
the state of integrity. But in corrupt nature the inclination of
concupiscence prevails, because it is dominant in man. Hence man is more
prone to bear evils for the sake of goods in which the concupiscence
delights here and now, than to endure evils for the sake of goods to
come, which are desired in accordance with reason: and yet it is this
that pertains to true patience.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The good of a social virtue [*Cf. FS, Q[61], A[5]] is
commensurate with human nature; and consequently the human will can tend
thereto without the help of sanctifying grace, yet not without the help
of God's grace [*Cf. FS, Q[109], A[2]]. On the other hand, the good of
grace is supernatural, wherefore man cannot tend thereto by a natural
virtue. Hence the comparison fails.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Even the endurance of those evils which a man bears for the
sake of his body's health, proceeds from the love a man naturally has for his own flesh. Hence there is no comparison between this endurance and
patience which proceeds from a supernatural love.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether patience is a part of fortitude?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that patience is not a part of fortitude. For a thing is
not part of itself. Now patience is apparently the same as fortitude:
because, as stated above (Q[123], A[6]), the proper act of fortitude is
to endure; and this belongs also to patience. For it is stated in the
Liber Sententiarum Prosperi [*The quotation is from St. Gregory, Hom.
xxxv in Evang.] that "patience consists in enduring evils inflicted by
others." Therefore patience is not a part of fortitude.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, fortitude is about fear and daring, as stated above
(Q[123], A[3]), and thus it is in the irascible. But patience seems to be
about sorrow, and consequently would seem to be in the concupiscible.
Therefore patience is not a part of fortitude but of temperance.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the whole cannot be without its part. Therefore if
patience is a part of fortitude, there can be no fortitude without
patience. Yet sometimes a brave man does not endure evils patiently, but
even attacks the person who inflicts the evil. Therefore patience is not
a part of fortitude.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Tully (De Invent. Rhet. ii) reckons it a part of
fortitude.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, Patience is a quasi-potential part of fortitude, because
it is annexed thereto as secondary to principal virtue. For it belongs to
patience "to suffer with an equal mind the evils inflicted by others," as
Gregory says in a homily (xxxv in Evang.). Now of those evils that are
inflicted by others, foremost and most difficult to endure are those that
are connected with the danger of death, and about these evils fortitude
is concerned. Hence it is clear that in this matter fortitude has the
principal place, and that it lays claim to that which is principal in
this matter. Wherefore patience is annexed to fortitude as secondary to
principal virtue, for which reason Prosper calls patience brave (Sent.
811).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: It belongs to fortitude to endure, not anything indeed, but
that which is most difficult to endure, namely dangers of death: whereas
it may pertain to patience to endure any kind of evil.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 2: The act of fortitude consists not only in holding fast to
good against the fear of future dangers, but also in not failing through
sorrow or pain occasioned by things present; and it is in the latter
respect that patience is akin to fortitude. Yet fortitude is chiefly
about fear, which of itself evokes flight which fortitude avoids; while
patience is chiefly about sorrow, for a man is said to be patient, not
because he does not fly, but because he behaves in a praiseworthy manner
by suffering [patiendo] things which hurt him here and now, in such a way
as not to be inordinately saddened by them. Hence fortitude is properly
in the irascible, while patience is in the concupiscible faculty.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2

Nor does this hinder patience from being a part of fortitude, because
the annexing of virtue to virtue does not regard the subject, but the
matter or the form. Nevertheless patience is not to be reckoned a part of
temperance, although both are in the concupiscible, because temperance is
only about those sorrows that are opposed to pleasures of touch, such as
arise through abstinence from pleasures of food and sex: whereas patience
is chiefly about sorrows inflicted by other persons. Moreover it belongs
to temperance to control these sorrows besides their contrary pleasures:
whereas it belongs to patience that a man forsake not the good of virtue
on account of such like sorrows, however great they be.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: It may be granted that patience in a certain respect is an
integral part of justice, if we consider the fact that a man may
patiently endure evils pertaining to dangers of death; and it is from
this point of view that the objection argues. Nor is it inconsistent with
patience that a man should, when necessary, rise up against the man who
inflicts evils on him; for Chrysostom [*Homily v. in the Opus
Imperfectum, falsely ascribed to St. John Chrysostom] says on Mt. 4:10,
"Begone Satan," that "it is praiseworthy to be patient under our own
wrongs, but to endure God's wrongs patiently is most wicked": and
Augustine says in a letter to Marcellinus (Ep. cxxxviii) that "the
precepts of patience are not opposed to the good of the commonwealth,
since in order to ensure that good we fight against our enemies." But in
so far as patience regards all kinds of evils, it is annexed to fortitude
as secondary to principal virtue.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether patience is the same as longanimity? [*Longsuffering. It is
necessary to preserve the Latin word, on account of the comparison with
magnanimity.]

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that patience is the same as longanimity. For Augustine
says (De Patientia i) that "we speak of patience in God, not as though
any evil made Him suffer, but because He awaits the wicked, that they may
be converted." Wherefore it is written (Ecclus. 5:4): "The Most High is a
patient rewarder." Therefore it seems that patience is the same as
longanimity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the same thing is not contrary to two things. But
impatience is contrary to longanimity, whereby one awaits a delay: for
one is said to be impatient of delay, as of other evils. Therefore it
seems that patience is the same as longanimity.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, just as time is a circumstance of wrongs endured, so is
place. But no virtue is distinct from patience on the score of place.
Therefore in like manner longanimity which takes count of time, in so far
as a person waits for a long time, is not distinct from patience.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: On the contrary, a gloss [*Origen, Comment. in Ep. ad Rom. ii] on
Rm. 2:4, "Or despisest thou the riches of His goodness, and patience, and
longsuffering?" says: "It seems that longanimity differs from patience,
because those who offend from weakness rather than of set purpose are
said to be borne with longanimity: while those who take a deliberate
delight in their crimes are said to be borne patiently."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Body Para. 1/4

I answer that, Just as by magnanimity a man has a mind to tend to great
things, so by longanimity a man has a mind to tend to something a long
way off. Wherefore as magnanimity regards hope, which tends to good,
rather than daring, fear, or sorrow, which have evil as their object, so
also does longanimity. Hence longanimity has more in common with
magnanimity than with patience.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Body Para. 2/4

Nevertheless it may have something in common with patience, for two
reasons. First, because patience, like fortitude, endures certain evils
for the sake of good, and if this good is awaited shortly, endurance is
easier: whereas if it be delayed a long time, it is more difficult.
Secondly, because the very delay of the good we hope for, is of a nature
to cause sorrow, according to Prov. 13:12, "Hope that is deferred
afflicteth the soul." Hence there may be patience in bearing this trial,
as in enduring any other sorrows. Accordingly longanimity and constancy
are both comprised under patience, in so far as both the delay of the
hoped for good (which regards longanimity) and the toil which man endures
in persistently accomplishing a good work (which regards constancy) may
be considered under the one aspect of grievous evil.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Body Para. 3/4

For this reason Tully (De Invent. Rhet. ii) in defining patience, says
that "patience is the voluntary and prolonged endurance of arduous and
difficult things for the sake of virtue or profit." By saying "arduous"
he refers to constancy in good; when he says "difficult" he refers to the
grievousness of evil, which is the proper object of patience; and by
adding "continued" or "long lasting," he refers to longanimity, in so far
as it has something in common with patience.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] Body Para. 4/4

This suffices for the Replies to the First and Second Objections.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 3: That which is a long way off as to place, though distant
from us, is not simply distant from things in nature, as that which is a
long way off in point of time: hence the comparison fails. Moreover, what
is remote as to place offers no difficulty save in the point of time,
since what is placed a long way from us is a long time coming to us.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[136] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2

We grant the fourth argument. We must observe, however, that the reason
for the difference assigned by this gloss is that it is hard to bear with
those who sin through weakness, merely because they persist a long time
in evil, wherefore it is said that they are borne with longanimity:
whereas the very fact of sinning through pride seems to be unendurable;
for which reason those who sin through pride are stated to be borne with
patience.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License