Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] Out. Para. 1/1 - INTEGRAL PARTS OF TEMPERANCE (QQ[144]-154)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] Out. Para. 1/1 - INTEGRAL PARTS OF TEMPERANCE (QQ[144]-154)


OF SHAMEFACEDNESS (FOUR ARTICLES)

We must now consider the parts of temperance in particular: and in the
first place the integral parts, which are shamefacedness and honesty.
With regard to shamefacedness there are four points of inquiry:

(1) Whether shamefacedness is a virtue?

(2) What is its object?

(3) Who are the cause of a man being ashamed?

(4) What kind of people are ashamed?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether shamefacedness is a virtue?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It seems that shamefacedness is a virtue. For it is proper to a
virtue "to observe the mean as fixed by reason": this is clear from the
definition of virtue given in Ethic. ii, 6. Now shamefacedness observes
the mean in this way, as the Philosopher observes (Ethic. ii, 7).
Therefore shamefacedness is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, whatever is praiseworthy is either a virtue or something
connected with virtue. Now shamefacedness is praiseworthy. But it is not
part of a virtue. For it is not a part of prudence, since it is not in
the reason but in the appetite; nor is it a part of justice. since
shamefacedness implies a certain passion, whereas justice is not about
the passions; nor again is it a part of fortitude, because it belongs to
fortitude to be persistent and aggressive, while it belongs to
shamefacedness to recoil from something; nor lastly is it a part of
temperance, since the latter is about desires, whereas shamefacedness is
a kind of fear according as the Philosopher states (Ethic. iv, 9) and
Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 15). Hence it follows that shamefacedness is
a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the honest and the virtuous are convertible according to Tully (De Offic. i, 27). Now shamefacedness is a part of honesty: for
Ambrose says (De Offic. i, 43) that "shamefacedness is the companion and
familiar of the restful mind, averse to wantonness, a stranger to any
kind of excess, the friend of sobriety and the support of what is honest,
a seeker after the beautiful." Therefore shamefacedness is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, every vice is opposed to a virtue. Now certain vices are
opposed to shamefacedness, namely shamelessness and inordinate prudery.
Therefore shamefacedness is a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, "like acts beget like habits," according to Ethic. ii,
1. Now shamefacedness implies a praiseworthy act; wherefore from many
such acts a habit results. But a habit of praiseworthy deeds is a virtue,
according to the Philosopher (Ethic. i, 12). Therefore shamefacedness is
a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 7; iv, 9) that
shamefacedness is not a virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Virtue is taken in two ways, in a strict sense and in a
broad sense. Taken strictly virtue is a perfection, as stated in Phys.
vii, 17,18. Wherefore anything that is inconsistent with perfection,
though it be good, falls short of the notion of virtue. Now
shamefacedness is inconsistent with perfection, because it is the fear of
something base, namely of that which is disgraceful. Hence Damascene says
(De Fide Orth. ii, 15) that "shamefacedness is fear of a base action."
Now just as hope is about a possible and difficult good, so is fear about
a possible and arduous evil, as stated above (FS, Q[40], A[1]; FS, Q[41],
A[2]; FS, Q[42], A[3]), when we were treating of the passions. But one
who is perfect as to a virtuous habit, does not apprehend that which
would be disgraceful and base to do, as being possible and arduous, that
is to say difficult for him to avoid; nor does he actually do anything
base, so as to be in fear of disgrace. Therefore shamefacedness, properly
speaking, is not a virtue, since it falls short of the perfection of
virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] Body Para. 2/2

Taken, however, in a broad sense virtue denotes whatever is good and
praiseworthy in human acts or passions; and in this way /shamefacedness
is sometimes called a virtue, since it is a praiseworthy passion.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Observing the mean is not sufficient for the notion of
virtue, although it is one of the conditions included in virtue's
definition: but it is requisite, in addition to this, that it be "an
elective habit," that is to say, operating from choice. Now
shamefacedness denotes, not a habit but a passion, nor does its movement
result from choice, but from an impulse of passion. Hence it falls short
of the notion of virtue.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: As stated above, shamefacedness is fear of baseness and
disgrace. Now it has been stated (Q[142], A[4]) that the vice of
intemperance is most base and disgraceful. Wherefore shamefacedness
pertains more to temperance than to any other virtue, by reason of its
motive cause, which is a base action though not according to the species
of the passion, namely fear. Nevertheless in so far as the vices opposed
to other virtues are base and disgraceful, shamefacedness may also
pertain to other virtues.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Shamefacedness fosters honesty, by removing that which is
contrary thereto, but not so as to attain to the perfection of honesty.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Every defect causes a vice, but not every good is
sufficient for the notion of virtue. Consequently it does not follow that
whatever is directly opposed to vice is a virtue, although every vice is
opposed to a virtue, as regards its origin. Hence shamelessness, in so
far as it results from excessive love of disgraceful things, is opposed
to temperance.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: Being frequently ashamed causes the habit of an acquired
virtue whereby one avoids disgraceful things which are the object of
shamefacedness, without continuing to be ashamed in their regard:
although as a consequence of this acquired virtue, a man would be more
ashamed, if confronted with the matter of shamefacedness.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether shamefacedness is about a disgraceful action?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that shamefacedness is not about a disgraceful
action. For the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 9) that "shamefacedness is
fear of disgrace." Now sometimes those who do nothing wrong suffer
ignominy, according to Ps. 67:8, "For thy sake I have borne reproach,
shame hath covered my face." Therefore shamefacedness is not properly
about a disgraceful action.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, nothing apparently is disgraceful but what is sinful.
Yet man is ashamed of things that are not sins, for instance when he
performs a menial occupation. Therefore it seems that shamefacedness is
not properly about a disgraceful action.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, virtuous deeds are not disgraceful but most beautiful
according to Ethic. i, 8. Yet sometimes people are ashamed to do virtuous
deeds, according to Lk. 9:26, "He that shall be ashamed of Me and My
words, of him the Son of man shall be ashamed," etc. Therefore
shamefacedness is not about a disgraceful action.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, if shamefacedness were properly about a disgraceful
action, it would follow that the more disgraceful the action the more
ashamed would one be. Yet sometimes a man is more ashamed of lesser sins,
while he glories in those which are most grievous, according to Ps. 51:3,
"Why dost thou glory in malice?" Therefore shamefacedness is not properly
about a disgraceful action.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 15) and Gregory of Nyssa
[*Nemesius, (De Nat. Hom. xx)] say that "shamefacedness is fear of doing
a disgraceful deed or of a disgraceful deed done."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[41], A[2]; FS, Q[42], A[3]), when
we were treating of the passions, fear is properly about an arduous evil,
one, namely, that is difficult to avoid. Now disgrace is twofold. There
is the disgrace inherent to vice, which consists in the deformity of a
voluntary act: and this, properly speaking, has not the character of an
arduous evil. For that which depends on the will alone does not appear to
be arduous and above man's ability: wherefore it is not apprehended as
fearful, and for this reason the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that such
evils are not a matter of fear.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Body Para. 2/3

The other kind of disgrace is penal so to speak, and it consists in the
reproach that attaches to a person, just as the clarity of glory consists
in a person being honored. And since this reproach has the character of
an arduous evil, just as honor has the character of an arduous good,
shamefacedness, which is fear of disgrace, regards first and foremost
reproach or ignominy. And since reproach is properly due to vice, as
honor is due to virtue, it follows that shamefacedness regards also the
disgrace inherent to vice. Hence the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that
"a man is less ashamed of those defects which are not the result of any
fault of his own."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] Body Para. 3/3

Now shamefacedness regards fault in two ways. In one way a man refrains
from vicious acts through fear of reproach: in another way a man while
doing a disgraceful deed avoids the public eye through fear of reproach.
In the former case, according to Gregory of Nyssa (Nemesius, De Nat. Hom.
xx), we speak of a person "blushing," in the latter we say that he is
"ashamed." Hence he says that "the man who is ashamed acts in secret, but
he who blushes fears to be disgraced."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Shamefacedness properly regards disgrace as due to sin
which is a voluntary defect. Hence the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 6)
that "a man is more ashamed of those things of which he is the cause."
Now the virtuous man despises the disgrace to which he is subject on
account of virtue, because he does not deserve it; as the Philosopher
says of the magnanimous (Ethic. iv, 3). Thus we find it said of the
apostles (Acts 5:41) that "they (the apostles) went from the presence of
the council, rejoicing that they were accounted worthy to suffer reproach
for the name of Jesus." It is owing to imperfection of virtue that a man
is sometimes ashamed of the reproaches which he suffers on account of
virtue, since the more virtuous a man is, the more he despises external
things, whether good or evil. Wherefore it is written (Is. 51:7): "Fear
ye not the reproach of men."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: As stated above (Q[63], A[3]), though honor is not really
due save to virtue alone, yet it regards a certain excellence: and the
same applies to reproach, for though it is properly due to sin alone,
yet, at least in man's opinion, it regards any kind of defect. Hence a
man is ashamed of poverty, disrepute, servitude, and the like.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Shamefacedness does not regard virtuous deeds as such. Yet
it happens accidentally that a man is ashamed of them either because he
looks upon them as vicious according to human opinion, or because he is
afraid of being marked as presumptuous or hypocritical for doing virtuous
deeds.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Sometimes more grievous sins are less shameful, either
because they are less disgraceful, as spiritual sins in comparison with
sins of the flesh, or because they connote a certain abundance of some
temporal good; thus a man is more ashamed of cowardice than of daring, of
theft than of robbery, on account of a semblance of power. The same
applies to other sins.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether man is more shamefaced of those who are more closely connected
with him?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that man is not more shamefaced of those who are
more closely connected with him. For it is stated in Rhet. ii, 6 that
"men are more shamefaced of those from whom they desire approbation." Now
men desire this especially from people of the better sort who are
sometimes not connected with them. Therefore man is not more shamefaced
of those who are more closely connected with him.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, seemingly those are more closely connected who perform
like deeds. Now man is not made ashamed of his sin by those whom he knows
to be guilty of the same sin, because according to Rhet. ii, 6, "a man
does not forbid his neighbor what he does himself." Therefore he is not
more shamefaced of those who are most closely connected with him.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 6) that "men take more
shame from those who retail their information to many, such as jokers and
fable-tellers." But those who are more closely connected with a man do
not retail his vices. Therefore one should not take shame chiefly from
them.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 6) that "men are most
liable to be made ashamed by those among whom they have done nothing
amiss; by those of whom they ask something for the first time; by those
whose friends they wish to become." Now these are less closely connected
with us. Therefore man is not made most ashamed by those who are more
closely united to him.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is stated in Rhet. ii, 6 that "man is made most
ashamed by those who are to be continually with him."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, Since reproach is opposed to honor, just as honor denotes
attestation to someone's excellence, especially the excellence which is
according to virtue, so too reproach, the fear of which is
shamefacedness, denotes attestation to a person's defect, especially that
which results from sin. Hence the more weighty a person's attestation is
considered to be, the more does he make another person ashamed. Now a
person's attestation may be considered as being more weighty, either
because he is certain of the truth or because of its effect. Certitude of
the truth attaches to a person's attestations for two reasons. First on account of the rectitude of his judgement, as in the case of wise and
virtuous men, by whom man is more desirous of being honored and by whom
he is brought to a greater sense of shame. Hence children and the lower
animals inspire no one with shame, by reason of their lack of judgment.
Secondly, on account of his knowledge of the matter attested, because
"everyone judges well of what is known to him" [*Ethic. i, 3]. In this
way we are more liable to be made ashamed by persons connected with us,
since they are better acquainted with our deeds: whereas strangers and
persons entirely unknown to us, who are ignorant of what we do, inspire
us with no shame at all.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

An attestation receives weight from its effect by reason of some
advantage or harm resulting therefrom; wherefore men are more desirous of
being honored by those who can be of use to them, and are more liable to
be made ashamed by those who are able to do them some harm. And for this
reason again, in a certain respect, persons connected with us make us
more ashamed, since we are to be continually in their society, as though
this entailed a continual harm to us: whereas the harm that comes from
strangers and passersby ceases almost at once.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: People of the better sort make us ashamed for the same
reason as those who are more closely connected with us; because just as
the attestation of the better men carries more weight since they have a
more universal knowledge of things, and in their judgments hold fast to
the truth: so, too, the attestation of those among whom we live is more
cogent since they know more about our concerns in detail.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: We fear not the attestation of those who are connected with
us in the likeness of sin, because we do not think that they look upon
our defect as disgraceful.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Tale-bearers make us ashamed on account of the harm they do
by making many think ill of us.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Even those among whom we have done no wrong, make us more
ashamed, on account of the harm that would follow, because, to wit, we
should forfeit the good opinion they had of us: and again because when
contraries are put in juxtaposition their opposition seems greater, so
that when a man notices something disgraceful in one whom he esteemed
good, he apprehends it as being the more disgraceful. The reason why we
are made more ashamed by those of whom we ask something for the first
time, or whose friends we wish to be, is that we fear to suffer some
injury, by being disappointed in our request, or by failing to become
their friends.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether even virtuous men can be ashamed?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that even virtuous men can be ashamed. For
contraries have contrary effects. Now those who excel in wickedness are
not ashamed, according to Jer. 3:3, "Thou hadst a harlot's forehead, thou
wouldst not blush." Therefore those who are virtuous are more inclined to
be ashamed.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 6) that "men are ashamed
not only of vice, but also of the signs of evil": and this happens also
in the virtuous. Therefore virtuous men can be ashamed.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, shamefacedness is "fear of disgrace" [*Ethic. iv, 9].
Now virtuous people may happen to be ignominious, for instance if they
are slandered, or if they suffer reproach undeservedly. Therefore a
virtuous man can be ashamed.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, shamefacedness is a part of temperance, as stated above
(Q[143]). Now a part is not separated from its whole. Since then
temperance is in a virtuous man, it means that shamefacedness is also.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 9) that a "virtuous
man is not shamefaced."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (AA[1],2) shamefacedness is fear of some
disgrace. Now it may happen in two ways that an evil is not feared:
first, because it is not reckoned an evil; secondly because one reckons
it impossible with regard to oneself, or as not difficult to avoid.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

Accordingly shame may be lacking in a person in two ways. First, because
the things that should make him ashamed are not deemed by him to be
disgraceful; and in this way those who are steeped in sin are without
shame, for instead of disapproving of their sins, they boast of them.
Secondly, because they apprehend disgrace as impossible to themselves, or
as easy to avoid. In this way the old and the virtuous are not
shamefaced. Yet they are so disposed, that if there were anything
disgraceful in them they would be ashamed of it. Wherefore the
Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 9) that "shame is in the virtuous
hypothetically."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Lack of shame occurs in the best and in the worst men
through different causes, as stated in the Article. In the average men it
is found, in so far as they have a certain love of good, and yet are not
altogether free from evil.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: It belongs to the virtuous man to avoid not only vice, but
also whatever has the semblance of vice, according to 1 Thess. 5:22,
"From all appearance of evil refrain yourselves." The Philosopher, too,
says (Ethic. iv, 9) that the virtuous man should avoid "not only what is
really evil, but also those things that are regarded as evil."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: As stated above (A[1], ad 1) the virtuous man despises
ignominy and reproach, as being things he does not deserve, wherefore he
is not much ashamed of them. Nevertheless, to a certain extent, shame,
like the other passions, may forestall reason.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[144] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Shamefacedness is a part of temperance, not as though it
entered into its essence, but as a disposition to it: wherefore Ambrose
says (De Offic. i, 43) that "shamefacedness lays the first foundation of
temperance," by inspiring man with the horror of whatever is disgraceful.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License