Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • SECOND PART
    • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/4 - SECOND PART OF THE SECOND PART (SS) (QQ[1]-189)
      • Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF RELIGIOUS LIFE (EIGHT ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] Out. Para. 1/1 - OF THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF RELIGIOUS LIFE (EIGHT ARTICLES)

We must now consider the different kinds of religious life, and under
this head there are eight points of inquiry:

(1) Whether there are different kinds of religious life or only one?

(2) Whether a religious order can be established for the works of the
active life?

(3) Whether a religious order can be directed to soldiering?

(4) Whether a religious order can be established for preaching and the
exercise of like works?

(5) Whether a religious order can be established for the study of
science?

(6) Whether a religious order that is directed to the contemplative life
is more excellent than one that is directed to the active life?

(7) Whether religious perfection is diminished by possessing something
in common?

(8) Whether the religious life of solitaries is to be preferred to the
religious life of those who live in community?


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether there is only one religious order?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that there is but one religious order. For there
can be no diversity in that which is possessed wholly and perfectly;
wherefore there can be only one sovereign good, as stated in the FP, Q[6]
, AA[2],3,4. Now as Gregory says (Hom. xx in Ezech.), "when a man vows to
Almighty God all that he has, all his life, all his knowledge, it is a
holocaust," without which there is no religious life. Therefore it would
seem that there are not many religious orders but only one.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, things which agree in essentials differ only
accidentally. Now there is no religious order without the three essential
vows of religion, as stated above (Q[186], AA[6],7). Therefore it would
seem that religious orders differ not specifically, but only accidentally.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the state of perfection is competent both to religious
and to bishops, as stated above (Q[185], AA[5],7). Now the episcopate is
not diversified specifically, but is one wherever it may be; wherefore
Jerome says (Ep. cxlvi ad Evan.): "Wherever a bishop is, whether at Rome,
or Gubbio, or Constantinople, or Reggio, he has the same excellence, the
same priesthood." Therefore in like manner there is but one religious
order.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, anything that may lead to confusion should be removed
from the Church. Now it would seem that a diversity of religious orders
might confuse the Christian people, as stated in the Decretal de Statu
Monach. et Canon. Reg. [*Cap. Ne Nimia, de Relig. Dom.]. Therefore
seemingly there ought not to be different religious orders.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (Ps. 44:10) that it pertains to the
adornment of the queen that she is "surrounded with variety."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (Q[186], A, 7; Q[187], A[2]), the
religious state is a training school wherein one aims by practice at the
perfection of charity. Now there are various works of charity to which a
man may devote himself; and there are also various kinds of exercise.
Wherefore religious orders may be differentiated in two ways. First,
according to the different things to which they may be directed: thus one
may be directed to the lodging of pilgrims, another to visiting or
ransoming captives. Secondly, there may be various religious orders
according to the diversity of practices; thus in one religious order the
body is chastised by abstinence in food, in another by the practice of
manual labor, scantiness of clothes, or the like.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] Body Para. 2/2

Since, however, the end imports most in every matter, [*Arist., Topic.
vi 8] religious orders differ more especially according to their various
ends than according to their various practices.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The obligation to devote oneself wholly to God's service is
common to every religious order; hence religious do not differ in this
respect, as though in one religious order a person retained some one
thing of his own, and in another order some other thing. But the
difference is in respect of the different things wherein one may serve
God, and whereby a man may dispose himself to the service of God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The three essential vows of religion pertain to the
practice of religion as principles to which all other matters are
reduced, as stated above (Q[186], A[7]). But there are various ways of
disposing oneself to the observance of each of them. For instance one
disposes oneself to observe the vow of continence, by solitude of place,
by abstinence, by mutual fellowship, and by many like means. Accordingly
it is evident that the community of the essential vows is compatible with
diversity of religious life, both on account of the different
dispositions and on account of the different ends, as explained above.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: In matters relating to perfection, the bishop stands in the
position of agent, and the religious as passive, as stated above (Q[184],
A[7]). Now the agent, even in natural things, the higher it is, is so
much the more one, whereas the things that are passive are various. Hence
with reason the episcopal state is one, while religious orders are many.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Confusion is opposed to distinction and order. Accordingly
the multitude of religious orders would lead to confusion, if different
religious orders were directed to the same end and in the same way,
without necessity or utility. Wherefore to prevent this happening it has
been wholesomely forbidden to establish a new religious order without the
authority of the Sovereign Pontiff.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a religious order should be established for the works of the
active life?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that no religious order should be established for
the works of the active life. For every religious order belongs to the
state of perfection, as stated above (Q[184], A[5]; Q[186], A[1]). Now
the perfection of the religious state consists in the contemplation of
divine things. For Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. vi) that they are "called
servants of God by reason of their rendering pure service and subjection
to God, and on account of the indivisible and singular life which unites
them by holy reflections," i.e. contemplations, "on invisible things, to
the Godlike unity and the perfection beloved of God." Therefore seemingly
no religious order should be established for the works of the active life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, seemingly the same judgment applies to canons regular as
to monks, according to Extra, De Postul., cap. Ex parte; and De Statu
Monach., cap. Quod Dei timorem: for it is stated that "they are not
considered to be separated from the fellowship of monks": and the same
would seem to apply to all other religious. Now the monastic rule was
established for the purpose of the contemplative life; wherefore Jerome
says (Ep. lviii ad Paulin.): "If you wish to be what you are called, a
monk," i.e. a solitary, "what business have you in a city?" The same is
found stated in Extra, De Renuntiatione, cap. Nisi cum pridem; and De
Regular., cap. Licet quibusdam. Therefore it would seem that every
religious order is directed to the contemplative life, and none to the
active life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the active life is concerned with the present world. Now
all religious are said to renounce the world; wherefore Gregory says
(Hom. xx in Ezech.): "He who renounces this world, and does all the good
he can, is like one who has gone out of Egypt and offers sacrifice in the
wilderness." Therefore it would seem that no religious order can be
directed to the active life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is written (James 1:27): "Religion clean and
undefiled before God and the Father, is this: to visit the fatherless and
widows in their tribulation." Now this belongs to the active life.
Therefore religious life can be fittingly directed to the active life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (A[1]), the religious state is directed
to the perfection of charity, which extends to the love of God and of our
neighbor. Now the contemplative life which seeks to devote itself to God
alone belongs directly to the love of God, while the active life, which
ministers to our neighbor's needs, belongs directly to the love of one's
neighbor. And just as out of charity we love our neighbor for God's sake,
so the services we render our neighbor redound to God, according to Mt.
25:40, "What you have done [Vulg.: 'As long as you did it'] to one of
these My least brethren, you did it to Me." Consequently those services
which we render our neighbor, in so far as we refer them to God, are
described as sacrifices, according to Heb. 13:16, "Do not forget to do
good and to impart, for by such sacrifices God's favor is obtained." And
since it belongs properly to religion to offer sacrifice to God, as
stated above (Q[81], A[1], ad 1; A[4], ad 1), it follows that certain
religious orders are fittingly directed to the works of the active life.
Wherefore in the Conferences of the Fathers (Coll. xiv, 4) the Abbot
Nesteros in distinguishing the various aims of religious orders says:
"Some direct their intention exclusively to the hidden life of the desert
and purity of heart; some are occupied with the instruction of the
brethren and the care of the monasteries; while others delight in the
service of the guesthouse," i.e. in hospitality.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Service and subjection rendered to God are not precluded by
the works of the active life, whereby a man serves his neighbor for God's
sake, as stated in the Article. Nor do these works preclude singularity
of life; not that they involve man's living apart from his fellow-men,
but in the sense that each man individually devotes himself to things
pertaining to the service of God; and since religious occupy themselves
with the works of the active life for God's sake, it follows that their
action results from their contemplation of divine things. Hence they are
not entirely deprived of the fruit of the contemplative life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The same judgment applies to monks and to all other
religious, as regards things common to all religious orders: for instance
as regards their devoting themselves wholly to the divine service, their
observance of the essential vows of religion, and their refraining from
worldly business. But it does not follow that this likeness extends to
other things that are proper to the monastic profession, and are directed
especially to the contemplative life. Hence in the aforesaid Decretal, De
Postulando, it is not simply stated that "the same judgment applies to
canons regular" as "to monks," but that it applies "in matters already
mentioned," namely that "they are not to act as advocates in lawsuits."
Again the Decretal quoted, De Statu Monach., after the statement that
"canons regular are not considered to be separated from the fellowship of
monks," goes on to say: "Nevertheless they obey an easier rule." Hence it
is evident that they are not bound to all that monks are bound.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: A man may be in the world in two ways: in one way by his
bodily presence, in another way by the bent of his mind. Hence our Lord
said to His disciples (Jn. 15:19): "I have chosen you out of the world,"
and yet speaking of them to His Father He said (Jn. 17:11): "These are in
the world, and I come to Thee." Although, then, religious who are
occupied with the works of the active life are in the world as to the
presence of the body, they are not in the world as regards their bent of
mind, because they are occupied with external things, not as seeking
anything of the world, but merely for the sake of serving God: for "they
. . . use this world, as if they used it not," to quote 1 Cor. 7:31.
Hence (James 1:27) after it is stated that "religion clean and undefiled
. . . is . . . to visit the fatherless and widows in their tribulation,"
it is added, "and to keep one's self unspotted from this world," namely
to avoid being attached to worldly things.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a religious order can be directed to soldiering?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that no religious order can be directed to
soldiering. For all religious orders belong to the state of perfection.
Now our Lord said with reference to the perfection of Christian life (Mt.
5:39): "I say to you not to resist evil; but if one strike thee on the
right cheek, turn to him also the other," which is inconsistent with the
duties of a soldier. Therefore no religious order can be established for
soldiering.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the bodily encounter of the battlefield is more grievous
than the encounter in words that takes place between counsel at law. Yet
religious are forbidden to plead at law, as appears from the Decretal De
Postulando quoted above (A[2], OBJ[2]). Therefore it is much less seemly
for a religious order to be established for soldiering.
Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the religious state is a state of penance, as we have
said above (Q[187], A[6]). Now according to the code of laws soldiering
is forbidden to penitents. for it is said in the Decretal De Poenit.,
Dist. v, cap. 3: "It is altogether opposed to the rules of the Church, to
return to worldly soldiering after doing penance." Therefore it is
unfitting for any religious order to be established for soldiering.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, no religious order may be established for an unjust
object. But as Isidore says (Etym. xviii, 1), "A just war is one that is
waged by order of the emperor." Since then religious are private
individuals, it would seem unlawful for them to wage war; and
consequently no religious order may be established for this purpose.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (Ep. clxxxix; ad Bonifac.), "Beware of
thinking that none of those can please God who handle war-like weapons.
Of such was holy David to whom the Lord gave great testimony." Now
religious orders are established in order that men may please God.
Therefore nothing hinders the establishing of a religious order for the
purpose of soldiering.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, As stated above (A[2]), a religious order may be
established not only for the works of the contemplative life, but also
for the works of the active life, in so far as they are concerned in
helping our neighbor and in the service of God, but not in so far as they
are directed to a worldly object. Now the occupation of soldiering may be
directed to the assistance of our neighbor, not only as regards private
individuals, but also as regards the defense of the whole commonwealth.
Hence it is said of Judas Machabeus (1 Macc. 3:2,3) that "he [Vulg.:
'they'] fought with cheerfulness the battle of Israel, and he got his
people great honor." It can also be directed to the upkeep of divine
worship, wherefore (1 Macc. 3:21) Judas is stated to have said: "We will
fight for our lives and our laws," and further on (1 Macc. 13:3) Simon
said: "You know what great battles I and my brethren, and the house of my
father, have fought for the laws and the sanctuary."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

Hence a religious order may be fittingly established for soldiering, not
indeed for any worldly purpose, but for the defense of divine worship and
public safety, or also of the poor and oppressed, according to Ps. 81:4:
"Rescue the poor, and deliver the needy out of the hand of the sinner."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Not to resist evil may be understood in two ways. First, in
the sense of forgiving the wrong done to oneself, and thus it may pertain
to perfection, when it is expedient to act thus for the spiritual welfare
of others. Secondly, in the sense of tolerating patiently the wrongs done
to others: and this pertains to imperfection, or even to vice, if one be
able to resist the wrongdoer in a becoming manner. Hence Ambrose says (De
Offic. i, 27): "The courage whereby a man in battle defends his country
against barbarians, or protects the weak at home, or his friends against
robbers is full of justice": even so our Lord says in the passage quoted
[*Lk. 6:30 "Of him that taketh away thy goods, ask them not again"; Cf.
Mt. 5:40], " . . . thy goods, ask them not again." If, however, a man
were not to demand the return of that which belongs to another, he would
sin if it were his business to do so: for it is praiseworthy to give away
one's own, but not another's property. And much less should the things of
God be neglected, for as Chrysostom [*Hom. v in Matth. in the Opus
Imperfectum, falsely ascribed to St. John Chrysostom] says, "it is most
wicked to overlook the wrongs done to God."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: It is inconsistent with any religious order to act as
counsel at law for a worldly object, but it is not inconsistent to do so
at the orders of one's superior and in favor of one's monastery, as
stated in the same Decretal, or for the defense of the poor and widows.
Wherefore it is said in the Decretals (Dist. lxxxviii, cap. 1): "The holy
synod has decreed that henceforth no cleric is to buy property or occupy
himself with secular business, save with a view to the care of the
fatherless . . . and widows." Likewise to be a soldier for the sake of
some worldly object is contrary to all religious life, but this does not
apply to those who are soldiers for the sake of God's service.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Worldly soldiering is forbidden to penitents, but the
soldiering which is directed to the service of God is imposed as a
penance on some people, as in the case of those upon whom it is enjoined
to take arms in defense of the Holy Land.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: The establishment of a religious order for the purpose of
soldiering does not imply that the religious can wage war on their own
authority; but they can do so only on the authority of the sovereign or
of the Church.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a religious order can be established for preaching or hearing
confessions?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that no religious order may be established for
preaching, or hearing confessions. For it is said (VII, qu. i [*Cap. Hoc
nequaquam; Cf. Q[187], A[1], OBJ[1]]): "The monastic life is one of
subjection and discipleship, not of teaching, authority, or pastoral
care," and the same apparently applies to religious. Now preaching and
hearing confessions are the actions of a pastor and teacher. Therefore a
religious order should not be established for this purpose.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the purpose for which a religious order is established
would seem to be something most proper to the religious life, as stated
above (A[1]). Now the aforesaid actions are not proper to religious but
to bishops. Therefore a religious order should not be established for the
purpose of such actions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, it seems unfitting that the authority to preach and hear
confessions should be committed to an unlimited number of men; and there
is no fixed number of those who are received into a religious order.
Therefore it is unfitting for a religious order to be established for the
purpose of the aforesaid actions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, preachers have a right to receive their livelihood from
the faithful of Christ, according to 1 Cor. 9. If then the office of
preaching be committed to a religious order established for that purpose,
it follows that the faithful of Christ are bound to support an unlimited
number of persons, which would be a heavy burden on them. Therefore a
religious order should not be established for the exercise of these
actions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, the organization of the Church should be in accordance
with Christ's institution. Now Christ sent first the twelve apostles to
preach, as related in Luke 9, and afterwards He sent the seventy-two
disciples, as stated in Luke 10. Moreover, according to the gloss of Bede
on "And after these things" (Lk. 10:1), "the apostles are represented by
the bishops, the seventy-two disciples by the lesser priests," i.e. the
parish priests. Therefore in addition to bishops and parish priests, no
religious order should be established for the purpose of preaching and
hearing confessions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, In the Conferences of the Fathers (Coll. xiv, 4), Abbot
Nesteros, speaking of the various kinds of religious orders, says: "Some
choosing the care of the sick, others devoting themselves to the relief
of the afflicted and oppressed, or applying themselves to teaching, or
giving alms to the poor, have been most highly esteemed on account of
their devotion and piety." Therefore just as a religious order may be
established for the care of the sick, so also may one be established for
teaching the people by preaching and like works.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As stated above (A[2]), it is fitting for a religious
order to be established for the works of the active life, in so far as
they are directed to the good of our neighbor, the service of God, and
the upkeep of divine worship. Now the good of our neighbor is advanced by
things pertaining to the spiritual welfare of the soul rather than by
things pertaining to the supplying of bodily needs, in proportion to the
excellence of spiritual over corporal things. Hence it was stated above
(Q[32], A[3]) that spiritual works of mercy surpass corporal works of
mercy. Moreover this is more pertinent to the service of God, to Whom no
sacrifice is more acceptable than zeal for souls, as Gregory says (Hom.
xii in Ezech.). Furthermore, it is a greater thing to employ spiritual
arms in defending the faithful against the errors of heretics and the
temptations of the devil, than to protect the faithful by means of bodily
weapons. Therefore it is most fitting for a religious order to be
established for preaching and similar works pertaining to the salvation
of souls.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: He who works by virtue of another, acts as an instrument.
And a minister is like an "animated instrument," as the Philosopher says
(Polit. i, 2 [*Cf. Ethic. viii, 11]). Hence if a man preach or do
something similar by the authority of his superiors, he does not rise
above the degree of "discipleship" or "subjection," which is competent to
religious.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Some religious orders are established for soldiering, to
wage war, not indeed on their own authority, but on that of the sovereign
or of the Church who are competent to wage war by virtue of their office,
as stated above (A[3], ad 4). In the same way certain religious orders
are established for preaching and hearing confessions, not indeed by
their own authority, but by the authority of the higher and lower
superiors, to whom these things belong by virtue of their office.
Consequently to assist one's superiors in such a ministry is proper to a
religious order of this kind.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Bishops do not allow these religious severally and
indiscriminately to preach or hear confessions, but according to the
discretion of the religious superiors, or according to their own
appointment.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: The faithful are not bound by law to contribute to the
support of other than their ordinary prelates, who receive the tithes and
offerings of the faithful for that purpose, as well as other
ecclesiastical revenues. But if some men are willing to minister to the
faithful by exercising the aforesaid acts gratuitously, and without
demanding payment as of right, the faithful are not burdened thereby
because their temporal contributions can be liberally repaid by those
men, nor are they bound by law to contribute, but by charity, and yet not
so that they be burdened thereby and others eased, as stated in 2 Cor.
8:13. If, however, none be found to devote themselves gratuitously to
services of this kind, the ordinary prelate is bound, if he cannot
suffice by himself, to seek other suitable persons and support them
himself.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: The seventy-two disciples are represented not only by the
parish priests, but by all those of lower order who in any way assist the
bishops in their office. For we do not read that our Lord appointed the
seventy-two disciples to certain fixed parishes, but that "He sent them
two and two before His face into every city and place whither He Himself
was to come." It was fitting, however, that in addition to the ordinary
prelates others should be chosen for these duties on account of the
multitude of the faithful, and the difficulty of finding a sufficient
number of persons to be appointed to each locality, just as it was
necessary to establish religious orders for military service, on account
of the secular princes being unable to cope with unbelievers in certain
countries.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a religious order should be established for the purpose of study?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that a religious order should not be established
for the purpose of study. For it is written (Ps. 70:15,16): "Because I
have not known letters [Douay: 'learning'], I will enter into the powers
of the Lord," i.e. "Christian virtue," according to a gloss. Now the
perfection of Christian virtue, seemingly, pertains especially to
religious. Therefore it is not for them to apply themselves to the study
of letters.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, that which is a source of dissent is unbecoming to
religious, who are gathered together in the unity of peace. Now study
leads to dissent: wherefore different schools of thought arose among the
philosophers. Hence Jerome (Super Epist. ad Tit. 1:5) says: "Before a diabolical instinct brought study into religion, and people said: I am of
Paul, I of Apollo, I of Cephas," etc. Therefore it would seem that no
religious order should be established for the purpose of study.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, those who profess the Christian religion should profess
nothing in common with the Gentiles. Now among the Gentiles were some who
professed philosophy, and even now some secular persons are known as
professors of certain sciences. Therefore the study of letters does not
become religious.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Jerome (Ep. liii ad Paulin.) urges him to acquire
learning in the monastic state, saying: "Let us learn on earth those
things the knowledge of which will remain in heaven," and further on:
"Whatever you seek to know, I will endeavor to know with you."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that As stated above (A[2]), religion may be ordained to the
active and to the contemplative life. Now chief among the works of the
active life are those which are directly ordained to the salvation of
souls, such as preaching and the like. Accordingly the study of letters
is becoming to the religious life in three ways. First, as regards that
which is proper to the contemplative life, to which the study of letters
helps in a twofold manner. In one way by helping directly to contemplate,
namely by enlightening the intellect. For the contemplative life of which
we are now speaking is directed chiefly to the consideration of divine
things, as stated above (Q[180], A[4]), to which consideration man is
directed by study; for which reason it is said in praise of the righteous
(Ps. 1:2) that "he shall meditate day and night" on the law of the Lord,
and (Ecclus. 39:1): "The wise man will seek out the wisdom of all the
ancients, and will be occupied in the prophets." In another way the study
of letters is a help to the contemplative life indirectly, by removing
the obstacles to contemplation, namely the errors which in the
contemplation of divine things frequently beset those who are ignorant of
the scriptures. Thus we read in the Conferences of the Fathers (Coll. x,
3) that the Abbot Serapion through simplicity fell into the error of the
Anthropomorphites, who thought that God had a human shape. Hence Gregory
says (Moral. vi) that "some through seeking in contemplation more than
they are able to grasp, fall away into perverse doctrines, and by failing
to be the humble disciples of truth become the masters of error." Hence
it is written (Eccles. 2:3): "I thought in my heart to withdraw my flesh
from wine, that I might turn my mind to wisdom and might avoid folly."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Body Para. 2/3

Secondly, the study of letters is necessary in those religious orders
that are founded for preaching and other like works; wherefore the
Apostle (Titus 1:9), speaking of bishops to whose office these acts
belong, says: "Embracing that faithful word which is according to
doctrine, that he may be able to exhort in sound doctrine and to convince
the gainsayers." Nor does it matter that the apostles were sent to preach
without having studied letters, because, as Jerome says (Ep. liii ad
Paulin.), "whatever others acquire by exercise and daily meditation in
God's law, was taught them by the Holy Ghost."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] Body Para. 3/3

Thirdly, the study of letters is becoming to religious as regards that
which is common to all religious orders. For it helps us to avoid the
lusts of the flesh; wherefore Jerome says (Ep. cxxv ad Rust. Monach.):
"Love the science of the Scriptures and thou shalt have no love for
carnal vice." For it turns the mind away from lustful thoughts, and tames
the flesh on account of the toil that study entails according to Ecclus.
31:1, "Watching for riches* consumeth the flesh." [*Vigilia honestatis
St. Thomas would seem to have taken 'honestas' in the sense of virtue].
It also helps to remove the desire of riches, wherefore it is written
(Wis. 7:8): "I . . . esteemed riches nothing in comparison with her," and
(1 Macc. 12:9): "We needed none of these things," namely assistance from
without, "having for our comfort the holy books that are in our hands."
It also helps to teach obedience, wherefore Augustine says (De oper.
Monach. xvii): "What sort of perverseness is this, to wish to read, but
not to obey what one reads?" Hence it is clearly fitting that a religious
order be established for the study of letters.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: This commentary of the gloss is an exposition of the Old
Law of which the Apostle says (2 Cor. 3:6): "The letter killeth." Hence
not to know letters is to disapprove of the circumcision of the "letter"
and other carnal observances.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Study is directed to knowledge which, without charity,
"puffeth up," and consequently leads to dissent, according to Prov.
13:10, "Among the proud there are always dissensions": whereas, with
charity, it "edifieth and begets concord." Hence the Apostle after saying
(1 Cor. 1:5): "You are made rich . . . in all utterance and in all
knowledge," adds (1 Cor. 1:10): "That you all speak the same thing, and
that there be no schisms among you." But Jerome is not speaking here of
the study of letters, but of the study of dissensions which heretics and
schismatics have brought into the Christian religion.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The philosophers professed the study of letters in the
matter of secular learning: whereas it becomes religious to devote
themselves chiefly to the study of letters in reference to the doctrine
that is "according to godliness" (Titus 1:1). It becomes not religious,
whose whole life is devoted to the service of God, to seek for other
learning, save in so far as it is referred to the sacred doctrine. Hence
Augustine says at the end of De Musica vi, 17: "Whilst we think that we
should not overlook those whom heretics delude by the deceitful assurance
of reason and knowledge, we are slow to advance in the consideration of
their methods. Yet we should not be praised for doing this, were it not
that many holy sons of their most loving mother the Catholic Church had
done the same under the necessity of confounding heretics."


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether a religious order that is devoted to the contemplative life is
more excellent than on that is given to the active life?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that a religious order which is devoted to the
contemplative life is not more excellent than one which is given to the
active life. For it is said (Extra, de Regular. et Transeunt. ad Relig.,
cap. Licet), quoting the words of Innocent III: "Even as a greater good
is preferred to a lesser, so the common profit takes precedence of
private profit: and in this case teaching is rightly preferred to
silence, responsibility to contemplation, work to rest." Now the
religious order which is directed to the greater good is better.
Therefore it would seem that those religious orders that are directed to
the active life are more excellent than those which are directed to the
contemplative life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, every religious order is directed to the perfection of
charity, as stated above (AA[1],2). Now a gloss on Heb. 12:4, "For you
have not yet resisted unto blood," says: "In this life there is no more
perfect love than that to which the holy martyrs attained, who fought
against sin unto blood." Now to fight unto blood is becoming those
religious who are directed to military service, and yet this pertains to
the active life. Therefore it would seem that religious orders of this
kind are the most excellent.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, seemingly the stricter a religious order is, the more
excellent it is. But there is no reason why certain religious orders
directed to the active life should not be of stricter observance than
those directed to the contemplative life. Therefore they are more
excellent.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, our Lord said (Lk. 10:42) that the "best part" was
Mary's, by whom the contemplative life is signified.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Body Para. 1/3

I answer that, As stated above (A[1]), the difference between one
religious order and another depends chiefly on the end, and secondarily
on the exercise. And since one thing cannot be said to be more excellent
than another save in respect of that in which it differs therefrom, it
follows that the excellence of one religious order over another depends
chiefly on their ends, and secondarily on their respective exercises.
Nevertheless each of these comparisons is considered in a different way.
For the comparison with respect to the end is absolute, since the end is
sought for its own sake; whereas the comparison with respect to exercise
is relative, since exercise is sought not for its own sake, but for the
sake of the end. Hence a religious order is preferable to another, if it
be directed to an end that is absolutely more excellent either because it
is a greater good or because it is directed to more goods. If, however,
the end be the same, the excellence of one religious order over another
depends secondarily, not on the amount of exercise, but on the proportion
of the exercise to the end in view. Wherefore in the Conferences of the
Fathers (Coll. ii, 2) Blessed Antony is quoted, as preferring discretion
whereby a man moderates all his actions, to fastings, watchings, and all
such observances.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Body Para. 2/3

Accordingly we must say that the work of the active life is twofold. one
proceeds from the fulness of contemplation, such as teaching and
preaching. Wherefore Gregory says (Hom. v in Ezech.) that the words of
Ps. 144:7, "They shall publish the memory of . . . Thy sweetness," refer
"to perfect men returning from their contemplation." And this work is
more excellent than simple contemplation. For even as it is better to
enlighten than merely to shine, so is it better to give to others the
fruits of one's contemplation than merely to contemplate. The other work
of the active life consists entirely in outward occupation, for instance
almsgiving, receiving guests, and the like, which are less excellent than
the works of contemplation, except in cases of necessity, as stated
above (Q[182], A[1]). Accordingly the highest place in religious orders
is held by those which are directed to teaching and preaching, which,
moreover, are nearest to the episcopal perfection, even as in other
things "the end of that which is first is in conjunction with the
beginning of that which is second," as Dionysius states (Div. Nom. vii).
The second place belongs to those which are directed to contemplation,
and the third to those which are occupied with external actions.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] Body Para. 3/3

Moreover, in each of these degrees it may be noted that one religious
order excels another through being directed to higher action in the same
genus; thus among the works of the active life it is better to ransom
captives than to receive guests, and among the works of the contemplative
life prayer is better than study. Again one will excel another if it be
directed to more of these actions than another, or if it have statutes
more adapted to the attainment of the end in view.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: This Decretal refers to the active life as directed to the
salvation of souls.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Those religious orders that are established for the purpose
of military service aim more directly at shedding the enemy's blood than
at the shedding of their own, which latter is more properly competent to
martyrs. Yet there is no reason why religious of this description should
not acquire the merit of martyrdom in certain cases, and in this respect
stand higher than other religious; even as in some cases the works of the
active life take precedence of contemplation.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Strictness of observances, as the Blessed Antony remarks
(Conferences of the Fathers; Coll. ii, 2), is not the chief object of
commendation in a religious order; and it is written (Is. 58:5): "Is this
such a fast as I have chosen, for a man to afflict his soul for a day?"
Nevertheless it is adopted in religious life as being necessary for
taming the flesh, "which if done without discretion, is liable to make us
fail altogether," as the Blessed Antony observes. Wherefore a religious
order is not more excellent through having stricter observances, but
because its observances are directed by greater discretion to the end of
religion. Thus the taming of the flesh is more efficaciously directed to
continence by means of abstinence in meat and drink, which pertain to
hunger and thirst, than by the privation of clothing, which pertains to
cold and nakedness, or by bodily labor.


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether religious perfection is diminished by possessing something in
common?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that religious perfection is diminished by
possessing something in common. For our Lord said (Mt. 19:21): "If thou
wilt be perfect, go sell all [Vulg.: 'what'] thou hast and give to the
poor." Hence it is clear that to lack worldly wealth belongs to the
perfection of Christian life. Now those who possess something in common
do not lack worldly wealth. Therefore it would seem that they do not
quite reach to the perfection of Christian life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the perfection of the counsels requires that one should
be without worldly solicitude; wherefore the Apostle in giving the
counsel of virginity said (1 Cor. 7:32): "I would have you to be without
solicitude." Now it belongs to the solicitude of the present life that
certain people keep something to themselves for the morrow; and this
solicitude was forbidden His disciples by our Lord (Mt. 6:34) saying: "Be
not . . . solicitous for tomorrow." Therefore it would seem that the
perfection of Christian life is diminished by having something in common.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, possessions held in common belong in some way to each
member of the community; wherefore Jerome (Ep. lx ad Heliod. Episc.) says
in reference to certain people: "They are richer in the monastery than
they had been in the world; though serving the poor Christ they have
wealth which they had not while serving the rich devil; the Church
rejects them now that they are rich, who in the world were beggars." But
it is derogatory to religious perfection that one should possess wealth
of one's own. Therefore it is also derogatory to religious perfection to
possess anything in common.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, Gregory (Dial. iii, 14) relates of a very holy man named
Isaac, that "when his disciples humbly signified that he should accept
the possessions offered to him for the use of the monastery, he being
solicitous for the safeguarding of his poverty, held firmly to his
opinion, saying: A monk who seeks earthly possessions is no monk at all":
and this refers to possessions held in common, and which were offered him
for the common use of the monastery. Therefore it would seem destructive
of religious perfection to possess anything in common.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, our Lord in prescribing religious perfection to His
disciples, said (Mt. 10:9,10): "Do not possess gold, nor silver, nor
money in your purses, nor script for your journey." By these words, as
Jerome says in his commentary, "He reproves those philosophers who are
commonly called Bactroperatae [*i.e. staff and scrip bearers], who as
despising the world and valuing all things at naught carried their pantry
about with them." Therefore it would seem derogatory to religious
perfection that one should keep something whether for oneself or for the
common use.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Prosper [*Julianus Pomerius, among the works of
Prosper] says (De Vita Contempl. ix) and his words are quoted (XII, qu.
1, can. Expedit): "It is sufficiently clear both that for the sake of
perfection one should renounce having anything of one's own, and that the
possession of revenues, which are of course common property, is no
hindrance to the perfection of the Church."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Body Para. 1/6

I answer that, As stated above (Q[184], A[3], ad 1; Q[185], A[6], ad 1),
perfection consists, essentially, not in poverty, but in following
Christ, according to the saying of Jerome (Super Matth. xix, 27): "Since
it is not enough to leave all, Peter adds that which is perfect, namely,
'We have followed Thee,'" while poverty is like an instrument or exercise
for the attainment of perfection. Hence in the Conferences of the Fathers
(Coll. i, 7) the abbot Moses says: "Fastings, watchings, meditating on
the Scriptures, poverty, and privation of all one's possessions are not
perfection, but means of perfection."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Body Para. 2/6

Now the privation of one's possessions, or poverty, is a means of
perfection, inasmuch as by doing away with riches we remove certain
obstacles to charity; and these are chiefly three. The first is the cares
which riches bring with them; wherefore our Lord said (Mt. 13:22): "That
which was sown [Vulg.: 'He that received the seed'] among thorns, is he
that heareth the word, and the care of this world, and the deceitfulness
of riches, choketh up the word." The second is the love of riches, which
increases with the possession of wealth; wherefore Jerome says (Super
Matth. xix, 23) that "since it is difficult to despise riches when we
have them, our Lord did not say: 'It is impossible for a rich man to
enter the kingdom of heaven,' but: 'It is difficult.'" The third is
vainglory or elation which results from riches, according to Ps. 48:7,
"They that trust in their own strength, and glory in the multitude of
their riches."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Body Para. 3/6

Accordingly the first of these three cannot be altogether separated from
riches whether great or small. For man must needs take a certain amount
of care in acquiring or keeping external things. But so long as external
things are sought or possessed only in a small quantity, and as much as
is required for a mere livelihood, such like care does not hinder one
much; and consequently is not inconsistent with the perfection of
Christian life. For our Lord did not forbid all care, but only such as is
excessive and hurtful; wherefore Augustine, commenting on Mt. 6:25, "Be
not solicitous for your life, what you shall eat," says (De Serm. in
Monte [*The words quoted are from De Operibus Monach. xxvi]): "In saying
this He does not forbid them to procure these things in so far as they
needed them, but to be intent on them, and for their sake to do whatever
they are bidden to do in preaching the Gospel." Yet the possession of
much wealth increases the weight of care, which is a great distraction to
man's mind and hinders him from giving himself wholly to God's service.
The other two, however, namely the love of riches and taking pride or
glorying in riches, result only from an abundance of wealth.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Body Para. 4/6

Nevertheless it makes a difference in this matter if riches, whether
abundant or moderate, be possessed in private or in common. For the care
that one takes of one's own wealth, pertains to love of self, whereby a
man loves himself in temporal matters; whereas the care that is given to
things held in common pertains to the love of charity which "seeketh not
her own," but looks to the common good. And since religion is directed to
the perfection of charity, and charity is perfected in "the love of God
extending to contempt of self" [*Augustine, De Civ. Dei xiv, 28], it is
contrary to religious perfection to possess anything in private. But the
care that is given to common goods may pertain to charity, although it
may prove an obstacle to some higher act of charity, such as divine
contemplation or the instructing of one's neighbor. Hence it is evident
that to have excessive riches in common, whether in movable or in
immovable property, is an obstacle to perfection, though not absolutely
incompatible with it; while it is not an obstacle to religious perfection
to have enough external things, whether movables or immovables, as
suffice for a livelihood, if we consider poverty in relation to the
common end of religious orders, which is to devote oneself to the service
of God. But if we consider poverty in relation to the special end of any
religious order, then this end being presupposed, a greater or lesser
degree of poverty is adapted to that religious order; and each religious
order will be the more perfect in respect of poverty, according as it
professes a poverty more adapted to its end. For it is evident that for
the purpose of the outward and bodily works of the active life a man
needs the assistance of outward things, whereas few are required for
contemplation. Hence the Philosopher says (Ethic. x, 8) that "many things
are needed for action, and the more so, the greater and nobler the
actions are. But the contemplative man requires no such things for the
exercise of his act: he needs only the necessaries; other things are an
obstacle to his contemplation." Accordingly it is clear that a religious
order directed to the bodily actions of the active life, such as
soldiering or the lodging of guests, would be imperfect if it lacked
common riches; whereas those religious orders which are directed to the
contemplative life are the more perfect, according as the poverty they
profess burdens them with less care for temporal things. And the care of
temporal things is so much a greater obstacle to religious life as the
religious life requires a greater care of spiritual things.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Body Para. 5/6

Now it is manifest that a religious order established for the purpose of
contemplating and of giving to others the fruits of one's contemplation
by teaching and preaching, requires greater care of spiritual things than
one that is established for contemplation only. Wherefore it becomes a
religious order of this kind to embrace a poverty that burdens one with
the least amount of care. Again it is clear that to keep what one has
acquired at a fitting time for one's necessary use involves the least
burden of care. Wherefore a threefold degree of poverty corresponds to
the three aforesaid degrees of religious life. For it is fitting that a
religious order which is directed to the bodily actions of the active
life should have an abundance of riches in common; that the common
possession of a religious order directed to contemplation should be more
moderate, unless the said religious be bound, either themselves or
through others, to give hospitality or to assist the poor; and that those
who aim at giving the fruits of their contemplation to others should have
their life most exempt from external cares; this being accomplished by
their laying up the necessaries of life procured at a fitting time. This,
our Lord, the Founder of poverty, taught by His example. For He had a
purse which He entrusted to Judas, and in which were kept the things that
were offered to Him, as related in Jn. 12:6.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] Body Para. 6/6

Nor should it be argued that Jerome (Super Matth. xvii, 26) says: "If
anyone object that Judas carried money in the purse, we answer that He
deemed it unlawful to spend the property of the poor on His own uses,"
namely by paying the tax - because among those poor His disciples held a
foremost place, and the money in Christ's purse was spent chiefly on
their needs. For it is stated (Jn. 4:8) that "His disciples were gone
into the city to buy meats," and (Jn. 13:29) that the disciples "thought,
because Judas had the purse, that Jesus had said to him: But those things
which we have need of for the festival day, or that he should give
something to the poor." From this it is evident that to keep money by, or
any other common property for the support of religious of the same order,
or of any other poor, is in accordance with the perfection which Christ
taught by His example. Moreover, after the resurrection, the disciples
from whom all religious orders took their origin kept the price of the
lands, and distributed it according as each one had need (Acts 4:34,35).

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: As stated above (Q[184], A[3], ad 1), this saying of our
Lord does not mean that poverty itself is perfection, but that it is the
means of perfection. Indeed, as shown above (Q[186], A[8]), it is the
least of the three chief means of perfection; since the vow of continence
excels the vow of poverty, and the vow of obedience excels them both.
Since, however, the means are sought not for their own sake, but for the
sake of the end, a thing is better, not for being a greater instrument,
but for being more adapted to the end. Thus a physician does not heal the
more the more medicine he gives, but the more the medicine is adapted to
the disease. Accordingly it does not follow that a religious order is the
more perfect, according as the poverty it professes is more perfect, but
according as its poverty is more adapted to the end both common and
special. Granted even that the religious order which exceeds others in
poverty be more perfect in so far as it is poorer, this would not make it
more perfect simply. For possibly some other religious order might
surpass it in matters relating to continence, or obedience, and thus be
more perfect simply, since to excel in better things is to be better
simply.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2

Reply OBJ 2: Our Lord's words (Mt. 6:34), "Be not solicitous for
tomorrow," do not mean that we are to keep nothing for the morrow; for
the Blessed Antony shows the danger of so doing, in the Conferences of
the Fathers (Coll. ii, 2), where he says: "It has been our experience
that those who have attempted to practice the privation of all means of
livelihood, so as not to have the wherewithal to procure themselves food
for one day, have been deceived so unawares that they were unable to
finish properly the work they had undertaken." And, as Augustine says (De
oper. Monach. xxiii), "if this saying of our Lord, 'Be not solicitous for
tomorrow,' means that we are to lay nothing by for the morrow, those who
shut themselves up for many days from the sight of men, and apply their
whole mind to a life of prayer, will be unable to provide themselves with
these things." Again he adds afterwards: "Are we to suppose that the
more holy they are, the less do they resemble the birds?" And further on
(De oper. Monach. xxiv): "For if it be argued from the Gospel that they
should lay nothing by, they answer rightly: Why then did our Lord have a
purse, wherein He kept the money that was collected? Why, in days long
gone by, when famine was imminent, was grain sent to the holy fathers?
Why did the apostles thus provide for the needs of the saints?"

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2

Accordingly the saying: "Be not solicitous for tomorrow," according to
Jerome (Super Matth.) is to be rendered thus: "It is enough that we think
of the present; the future being uncertain, let us leave it to God":
according to Chrysostom [*Hom. xvi in the Opus Imperfectum, falsely
ascribed to St. John Chrysostom], "It is enough to endure the toil for
necessary things, labor not in excess for unnecessary things": according
to Augustine (De Serm. Dom. in Monte ii, 17): "When we do any good
action, we should bear in mind not temporal things which are denoted by
the morrow, but eternal things."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The saying of Jerome applies where there are excessive
riches, possessed in private as it were, or by the abuse of which even
the individual members of a community wax proud and wanton. But they do
not apply to moderate wealth, set by for the common use, merely as a
means of livelihood of which each one stands in need. For it amounts to
the same that each one makes use of things pertaining to the necessaries
of life, and that these things be set by for the common use.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: Isaac refused to accept the offer of possessions, because
he feared lest this should lead him to have excessive wealth, the abuse
of which would be an obstacle to religious perfection. Hence Gregory adds
(Dial. iii, 14): "He was as afraid of forfeiting the security of his
poverty, as the rich miser is careful of his perishable wealth." It is
not, however, related that he refused to accept such things as are
commonly necessary for the upkeep of life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[7] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: The Philosopher says (Polit. i, 5,6) that bread, wine, and
the like are natural riches, while money is artificial riches. Hence it
is that certain philosophers declined to make use of money, and employed
other things, living according to nature. Wherefore Jerome shows by the
words of our Lord, Who equally forbade both, that it comes to the same to
have money and to possess other things necessary for life. And though our
Lord commanded those who were sent to preach not to carry these things on
the way, He did not forbid them to be possessed in common. How these
words of our Lord should be understood has been shown above (Q[185], A[6]
, ad 2; FS, Q[108], A[2], ad 3).


Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the religious life of those who live in community is more perfect
than that of those who lead a solitary life?

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the religious life of those who live in
community is more perfect than that of those who lead a solitary life.
For it is written (Eccles. 4:9): "It is better . . . that two should be
together, than one; for they have the advantage of their society."
Therefore the religious life of those who live in community would seem to
be more perfect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, it is written (Mt. 18:20): "Where there are two or three
gathered together in My name, there am I in the midst of them." But
nothing can be better than the fellowship of Christ. Therefore it would
seem better to live in community than in solitude.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the vow of obedience is more excellent than the other
religious vows; and humility is most acceptable to God. Now obedience and
humility are better observed in company than in solitude; for Jerome says
(Ep. cxxv ad Rustic. Monach.): "In solitude pride quickly takes man
unawares, he sleeps as much as he will, he does what he likes"; whereas
when instructing one who lives in community, he says: "You may not do
what you will, you must eat what you are bidden to eat, you may possess
so much as you receive, you must obey one you prefer not to obey, you
must be a servant to your brethren, you must fear the superior of the
monastery as God, love him as a father." Therefore it would seem that the
religious life of those who live in community is more perfect than that
of those who lead a solitary life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, our Lord said (Lk. 11:33): "No man lighteth a candle and
putteth it in a hidden place, nor under a bushel." Now those who lead a
solitary life are seemingly in a hidden place, and to be doing no good to
any man. Therefore it would seem that their religious life is not more
perfect.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

OBJ 5: Further, that which is in accord with man's nature is apparently
more pertinent to the perfection of virtue. But man is naturally a social
animal, as the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 1). Therefore it would seem
that to lead a solitary life is not more perfect than to lead a community
life.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine says (De oper. Monach. xxiii) that "those are
holier who keep themselves aloof from the approach of all, and give their
whole mind to a life of prayer."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Body Para. 1/4

I answer that, Solitude, like poverty, is not the essence of perfection,
but a means thereto. Hence in the Conferences of the Fathers (Coll. i, 7)
the Abbot Moses says that "solitude," even as fasting and other like
things, is "a sure means of acquiring purity of heart." Now it is evident
that solitude is a means adapted not to action but to contemplation,
according to Osee 2:14, "I . . . will lead her into solitude [Douay: 'the
wilderness']; and I will speak to her heart." Wherefore it is not
suitable to those religious orders that are directed to the works whether
corporal or spiritual of the active life; except perhaps for a time,
after the example of Christ, Who as Luke relates (6:12), "went out into a
mountain to pray; and He passed the whole night in the prayer of God."
On the other hand, it is suitable to those religious orders that are
directed to contemplation.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Body Para. 2/4

It must, however, be observed that what is solitary should be
self-sufficing by itself. Now such a thing is one "that lacks nothing,"
and this belongs to the idea of a perfect thing [*Aristotle, Phys. iii,
6]. Wherefore solitude befits the contemplative who has already attained
to perfection. This happens in two ways: in one way by the gift only of
God, as in the case of John the Baptist, who was "filled with the Holy Ghost even from his mother's womb" (Lk. 1:11), so that he was in the
desert even as a boy; in another way by the practice of virtuous action,
according to Heb. 5:14: "Strong meat is for the perfect; for them who by
custom have their senses exercised to the discerning of good and evil."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Body Para. 3/4

Now man is assisted in this practice by the fellowship of others in two
ways. First, as regards his intellect, to the effect of his being
instructed in that which he has to contemplate; wherefore Jerome says (ad
Rustic. Monach., Ep. cxxv): "It pleases me that you have the fellowship
of holy men, and teach not yourself. Secondly, as regards the affections,
seeing that man's noisome affections are restrained by the example and
reproof which he receives from others; for as Gregory says (Moral. xxx,
23), commenting on the words, "To whom I have given a house in the
wilderness" (Job 39:6), "What profits solitude of the body, if solitude
of the heart be lacking?" Hence a social life is necessary for the
practice of perfection. Now solitude befits those who are already
perfect; wherefore Jerome says (ad Rustic. Monach., Ep. cxxv): "Far from
condemning the solitary life, we have often commended it. But we wish the
soldiers who pass from the monastic school to be such as not to be
deterred by the hard noviciate of the desert, and such as have given
proof of their conduct for a considerable time.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] Body Para. 4/4

Accordingly, just as that which is already perfect surpasses that which
is being schooled in perfection, so the life of the solitaries, if duly
practiced, surpasses the community life. But if it be undertaken without
the aforesaid practice, it is fraught with very great danger, unless the
grace of God supply that which others acquire by practice, as in the case
of the Blessed Antony and the Blessed Benedict.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Solomon shows that two are better than one, on account of
the help which one affords the other either by "lifting him" up, or by
"warming him," i.e. giving him spiritual heat (Eccles. 4:10,11). But
those who have already attained to perfection do not require this help.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: According to 1 Jn. 4:16, "He that abideth in charity
abideth in God and God in him." Wherefore just as Christ is in the midst
of those who are united together in the fellowship of brotherly love, so
does He dwell in the heart of the man who devotes himself to divine
contemplation through love of God.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Actual obedience is required of those who need to be
schooled according to the direction of others in the attainment of
perfection; but those who are already perfect are sufficiently "led by
the spirit of God" so that they need not to obey others actually.
Nevertheless they have obedience in the preparedness of the mind.

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: As Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xix, 19), "no one is
forbidden to seek the knowledge of truth, for this pertains to a
praiseworthy leisure." That a man be placed "on a candlestick," does not
concern him but his superiors, and "if this burden is not placed on us,"
as Augustine goes on to say (De Civ. Dei xix, 19), "we must devote
ourselves to the contemplation of truth," for which purpose solitude is
most helpful. Nevertheless, those who lead a solitary life are most
useful to mankind. Hence, referring to them, Augustine says (De Morib.
Eccl. xxxi): "They dwell in the most lonely places, content to live on
water and the bread that is brought to them from time to time, enjoying
colloquy with God to whom they have adhered with a pure mind. To some
they seem to have renounced human intercourse more than is right: but
these understand not how much such men profit us by the spirit of their
prayers, what an example to us is the life of those whom we are forbidden
to see in the body."

Aquin.: SMT SS Q[188] A[8] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 5: A man may lead a solitary life for two motives. one is
because he is unable, as it were, to bear with human fellowship on
account of his uncouthness of mind; and this is beast-like. The other is
with a view to adhering wholly to divine things; and this is superhuman.
Hence the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 1) that "he who associates not with
others is either a beast or a god," i.e. a godly man.





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License