Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library
St. Thomas Aquinas
Summa Theologica

IntraText CT - Text

  • Aquin.: SMT TP Prologue Para. 1/3 - THIRD PART (TP) OF THE SUMMA THEOLOGICA (QQ[1]-90)
      • Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] Out. Para. 1/3 - OF THE MODE OF UNION ON THE PART OF THE HUMAN NATURE (SIX ARTICLES)
Previous - Next

Click here to hide the links to concordance


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] Out. Para. 1/3 - OF THE MODE OF UNION ON THE PART OF THE HUMAN NATURE (SIX ARTICLES)

We must now consider the union on the part of what was assumed. About
which we must consider first what things were assumed by the Word of God;
secondly, what were co-assumed, whether perfections or defects.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] Out. Para. 2/3

Now the Son of God assumed human nature and its parts. Hence a threefold
consideration arises. First, with regard to the nature; secondly, with
regard to its parts; thirdly, with regard to the order of the assumption.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] Out. Para. 3/3

Under the first head there are six points of inquiry:

(1) Whether human nature was more capable of being assumed than any
other nature?

(2) Whether He assumed a person?

(3) Whether He assumed a man?

(4) Whether it was becoming that He should assume human nature
abstracted from all individuals?

(5) Whether it was becoming that He should assume human nature in all
its individuals?

(6) Whether it was becoming that He should assume human nature in any
man begotten of the stock of Adam?


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether human nature was more assumable by the Son of God than any other
nature?

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that human nature is not more capable of being
assumed by the Son of God than any other nature. For Augustine says (Ep.
ad Volusianum cxxxvii): "In deeds wrought miraculously the whole reason
of the deed is the power of the doer." Now the power of God Who wrought
the Incarnation, which is a most miraculous work, is not limited to one
nature, since the power of God is infinite. Therefore human nature is not
more capable of being assumed than any other creature.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, likeness is the foundation of the fittingness of the
Incarnation of the Divine Person, as above stated (Q[3], A[8]). But as in
rational creatures we find the likeness of image, so in irrational
creatures we find the image of trace. Therefore the irrational creature
was as capable of assumption as human nature.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, in the angelic nature we find a more perfect likeness
than in human nature, as Gregory says: (Hom. de Cent. Ovib.; xxxiv in
Ev.), where he introduces Ezech. 28:12: "Thou wast the seal of
resemblance." And sin is found in angels, even as in man, according to
Job 4:18: "And in His angels He found wickedness." Therefore the angelic
nature was as capable of assumption as the nature of man.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

OBJ 4: Further, since the highest perfection belongs to God, the more
like to God a thing is, the more perfect it is. But the whole universe is
more perfect than its parts, amongst which is human nature. Therefore the
whole universe is more capable of being assumed than human nature.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, It is said (Prov. 8:31) by the mouth of Begotten
Wisdom: "My delights were to be with the children of men"; and hence
there would seem some fitness in the union of the Son of God with human
nature.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, A thing is said to be assumable as being capable of being
assumed by a Divine Person, and this capability cannot be taken with
reference to the natural passive power, which does not extend to what
transcends the natural order, as the personal union of a creature with
God transcends it. Hence it follows that a thing is said to be assumable
according to some fitness for such a union. Now this fitness in human
nature may be taken from two things, viz. according to its dignity, and
according to its need. According to its dignity, because human nature, as
being rational and intellectual, was made for attaining to the Word to
some extent by its operation, viz. by knowing and loving Him. According
to its need - because it stood in need of restoration, having fallen
under original sin. Now these two things belong to human nature alone.
For in the irrational creature the fitness of dignity is wanting, and in
the angelic nature the aforesaid fitness of need is wanting. Hence it
follows that only human nature was assumable.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Creatures are said to be "such" with reference to their
proper causes, not with reference to what belongs to them from their
first and universal causes; thus we call a disease incurable, not that it
cannot be cured by God, but that it cannot be cured by the proper
principles of the subject. Therefore a creature is said to be not
assumable, not as if we withdrew anything from the power of God, but in
order to show the condition of the creature, which has no capability for
this.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The likeness of image is found in human nature, forasmuch
as it is capable of God, viz. by attaining to Him through its own
operation of knowledge and love. But the likeness of trace regards only a
representation by Divine impression, existing in the creature, and does
not imply that the irrational creature, in which such a likeness is, can
attain to God by its own operation alone. For what does not come up to
the less, has no fitness for the greater; as a body which is not fitted
to be perfected by a sensitive soul is much less fitted for an
intellectual soul. Now much greater and more perfect is the union with
God in personal being than the union by operation. And hence the
irrational creature which falls short of the union with God by operation
has no fitness to be united with Him in personal being.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Some say that angels are not assumable, since they are
perfect in their personality from the beginning of their creation,
inasmuch as they are not subject to generation and corruption; hence they
cannot be assumed to the unity of a Divine Person, unless their
personality be destroyed, and this does not befit the incorruptibility of
their nature nor the goodness of the one assuming, to Whom it does not
belong to corrupt any perfection in the creature assumed. But this would
not seem totally to disprove the fitness of the angelic nature for being
assumed. For God by producing a new angelic nature could join it to
Himself in unity of Person, and in this way nothing pre-existing would be
corrupted in it. But as was said above, there is wanting the fitness of
need, because, although the angelic nature in some is the subject of sin,
their sin is irremediable, as stated above (FP, Q[64], A[2]).

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 4: The perfection of the universe is not the perfection of one
person or suppositum, but of something which is one by position or order,
whereof very many parts are not capable of assumption, as was said above.
Hence it follows that only human nature is capable of being assumed.


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the Son of God assumed a person?

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the Son of God assumed a person. For Damascene
says (De Fide Orth. iii, 11) that the Son of God "assumed human nature
'in atomo,'" i.e. in an individual. But an individual in rational nature
is a person, as is plain from Boethius (De Duab. Nat.). Therefore the Son
of God assumed a person.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 6) that the Son of
God "assumed what He had sown in our nature." But He sowed our
personality there. Therefore the Son of God assumed a person.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, nothing is absorbed unless it exist. But Innocent III
[*Paschas. Diac., De Spiritu Sanct. ii] says in a Decretal that "the
Person of God absorbed the person of man." Therefore it would seem that
the person of man existed previous to its being assumed.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Augustine [*Fulgentius] says (De Fide ad Petrum ii)
that "God assumed the nature, not the person, of man."

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, A thing is said to be assumed inasmuch as it is taken
into another. Hence, what is assumed must be presupposed to the
assumption, as what is moved locally is presupposed to the motion. Now a
person in human nature is not presupposed to assumption; rather, it is
the term of the assumption, as was said (Q[3], AA[1],2). For if it were
presupposed, it must either have been corrupted - in which case it was
useless; or it remains after the union - and thus there would be two
persons, one assuming and the other assumed, which is false, as was shown
above (Q[2], A[6]). Hence it follows that the Son of God nowise assumed a
human person.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The Son of God assumed human nature "in atomo," i.e. in an
individual, which is no other than the uncreated suppositum, the Person
of the Son of God. Hence it does not follow that a person was assumed.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Its proper personality is not wanting to the nature assumed
through the loss of anything pertaining to the perfection of the human
nature but through the addition of something which is above human nature,
viz. the union with a Divine Person.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Absorption does not here imply the destruction of anything
pre-existing, but the hindering what might otherwise have been. For if
the human nature had not been assumed by a Divine Person, the human
nature would have had its own personality; and in this way is it said,
although improperly, that the Person "absorbed the person," inasmuch as
the Divine Person by His union hindered the human nature from having its
personality.


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the Divine Person assumed a man?

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the Divine Person assumed a man. For it is
written (Ps. 64:5): "Blessed is he whom Thou hast chosen and taken to
Thee," which a gloss expounds of Christ; and Augustine says (De Agone
Christ. xi): "The Son of God assumed a man, and in him bore things human."

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the word "man" signifies a human nature. But the Son of
God assumed a human nature. Therefore He assumed a man.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the Son of God is a man. But He is not one of the men He
did not assume, for with equal reason He would be Peter or any other man.
Therefore He is the man whom He assumed.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Is the authority of Felix, Pope and Martyr, which is
quoted by the Council of Ephesus: "We believe in our Lord Jesus Christ,
born of the Virgin Mary, because He is the Eternal Son and Word of God,
and not a man assumed by God, in such sort that there is another besides
Him. For the Son of God did not assume a man, so that there be another
besides Him."

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As has been said above (A[2]), what is assumed is not the
term of the assumption, but is presupposed to the assumption. Now it was
said (Q[3], AA[1],2) that the individual to Whom the human nature is
assumed is none other than the Divine Person, Who is the term of the
assumption. Now this word "man" signifies human nature, as it is in a
suppositum, because, as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 4,11), this
word God signifies Him Who has human nature. And hence it cannot properly
be said that the Son assumed a man, granted (as it must be, in fact) that
in Christ there is but one suppositum and one hypostasis. But according
to such as hold that there are two hypostases or two supposita in Christ,
it may fittingly and properly be said that the Son of God assumed a man.
Hence the first opinion quoted in Sent. iii, D. 6, grants that a man was
assumed. But this opinion is erroneous, as was said above (Q[2], A[6]).

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: These phrases are not to be taken too literally, but are to
be loyally explained, wherever they are used by holy doctors; so as to
say that a man was assumed, inasmuch as his nature was assumed; and
because the assumption terminated in this - that the Son of God is man.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The word "man" signifies human nature in the concrete,
inasmuch as it is in a suppositum; and hence, since we cannot say a
suppositum was assumed, so we cannot say a man was assumed.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: The Son of God is not the man whom He assumed, but the man
whose nature He assumed.


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the Son of God ought to have assumed human nature abstracted from
all individuals?

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the Son of God ought to have assumed human
nature abstracted from all individuals. For the assumption of human
nature took place for the common salvation of all men; hence it is said
of Christ (1 Tim. 4:10) that He is "the Saviour of all men, especially of
the faithful." But nature as it is in individuals withdraws from its
universality. Therefore the Son of God ought to have assumed human nature
as it is abstracted from all individuals.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, what is noblest in all things ought to be attributed to
God. But in every genus what is of itself is best. Therefore the Son of
God ought to have assumed self-existing [per se] man, which, according to
Platonists, is human nature abstracted from its individuals. Therefore
the Son of God ought to have assumed this.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, human nature was not assumed by the Son of God in the
concrete as is signified by the word "man," as was said above (A[3]). Now
in this way it signifies human nature as it is in individuals, as is
plain from what has been said (A[3]). Therefore the Son of God assumed
human nature as it is separated from individuals.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 11): "God the Word
Incarnate did not assume a nature which exists in pure thought; for this
would have been no Incarnation, but a false and fictitious Incarnation."
But human nature as it is separated or abstracted from individuals is
"taken to be a pure conception, since it does not exist in itself," as
Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 11). Therefore the Son of God did not
assume human nature, as it is separated from individuals.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

I answer that, The nature of man or of any other sensible thing, beyond
the being which it has in individuals, may be taken in two ways: first,
as if it had being of itself, away from matter, as the Platonists held;
secondly, as existing in an intellect either human or Divine. Now it
cannot subsist of itself, as the Philosopher proves (Metaph. vii,
26,27,29,51), because sensible matter belongs to the specific nature of
sensible things, and is placed in its definition, as flesh and bones in
the definition of man. Hence human nature cannot be without sensible
matter. Nevertheless, if human nature were subsistent in this way, it
would not be fitting that it should be assumed by the Word of God. First,
because this assumption is terminated in a Person, and it is contrary to
the nature of a common form to be thus individualized in a person.
Secondly, because to a common nature can only be attributed common and
universal operations, according to which man neither merits nor demerits,
whereas, on the contrary, the assumption took place in order that the Son
of God, having assumed our nature, might merit for us. Thirdly, because a
nature so existing would not be sensible, but intelligible. But the Son
of God assumed human nature in order to show Himself in men's sight,
according to Baruch 3:38: "Afterwards He was seen upon earth, and
conversed with men."

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

Likewise, neither could human nature have been assumed by the Son of
God, as it is in the Divine intellect, since it would be none other than
the Divine Nature; and, according to this, human nature would be in the
Son of God from eternity. Neither can we say that the Son of God assumed
human nature as it is in a human intellect, for this would mean nothing
else but that He is understood to assume a human nature; and thus if He
did not assume it in reality, this would be a false understanding; nor
would this assumption of the human nature be anything but a fictitious
Incarnation, as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 11).

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: The incarnate Son of God is the common Saviour of all, not
by a generic or specific community, such as is attributed to the nature
separated from the individuals, but by a community of cause, whereby the
incarnate Son of God is the universal cause of human salvation.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: Self-existing [per se] man is not to be found in nature in
such a way as to be outside the singular, as the Platonists held,
although some say Plato believed that the separate man was only in the
Divine intellect. And hence it was not necessary for it to be assumed by
the Word, since it had been with Him from eternity.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Although human nature was not assumed in the concrete, as
if the suppositum were presupposed to the assumption, nevertheless it is
assumed in an individual, since it is assumed so as to be in an
individual.


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the Son of God ought to have assumed human nature in all
individuals?

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that the Son of God ought to have assumed human
nature in all individuals. For what is assumed first and by itself is
human nature. But what belongs essentially to a nature belongs to all who
exist in the nature. Therefore it was fitting that human nature should be
assumed by the Word of God in all its supposita.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, the Divine Incarnation proceeded from Divine Love; hence
it is written (Jn. 3:16): "God so loved the world as to give His
only-begotten Son." But love makes us give ourselves to our friends as
much as we can, and it was possible for the Son of God to assume several
human natures, as was said above (Q[3], A[7]), and with equal reason all.
Hence it was fitting for the Son of God to assume human nature in all its
supposita.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, a skilful workman completes his work in the shortest
manner possible. But it would have been a shorter way if all men had been
assumed to the natural sonship than for one natural Son to lead many to
the adoption of sons, as is written Gal. 4:5 (cf. Heb. 2:10). Therefore
human nature ought to have been assumed by God in all its supposita.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 11) that the Son of
God "did not assume human nature as a species, nor did He assume all its
hypostases."

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, It was unfitting for human nature to be assumed by the
Word in all its supposita. First, because the multitude of supposita of
human nature, which are natural to it, would have been taken away. For
since we must not see any other suppositum in the assumed nature, except
the Person assuming, as was said above (A[3]), if there was no human
nature except what was assumed, it would follow that there was but one
suppositum of human nature, which is the Person assuming. Secondly,
because this would have been derogatory to the dignity of the incarnate
Son of God, as He is the First-born of many brethren, according to the
human nature, even as He is the First-born of all creatures according to
the Divine, for then all men would be of equal dignity. Thirdly, because
it is fitting that as one Divine suppositum is incarnate, so He should
assume one human nature, so that on both sides unity might be found.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: To be assumed belongs to the human nature of itself,
because it does not belong to it by reason of a person, as it belongs to
the Divine Nature to assume by reason of the Person; not, however, that
it belongs to it of itself as if belonging to its essential principles,
or as its natural property in which manner it would belong to all its
supposita.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: The love of God to men is shown not merely in the
assumption of human nature, but especially in what He suffered in human
nature for other men, according to Rm. 5:8: "But God commendeth His
charity towards us; because when as yet we were sinners . . . Christ died
for us," which would not have taken place had He assumed human nature in
all its supposita.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: In order to shorten the way, which every skilful workman
does, what can be done by one must not be done by many. Hence it was most
fitting that by one man all the rest should be saved.


Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether it was fitting for the Son of God to assume human nature of the
stock of Adam?

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

OBJ 1: It would seem that it was not fitting for the Son of God to
assume human nature of the stock of Adam, for the Apostle says (Heb.
7:26): "For it was fitting that we should have such a high priest . . .
separated from sinners." But He would have been still further separated
from sinners had He not assumed human nature of the stock of Adam, a
sinner. Hence it seems that He ought not to have assumed human nature of
the stock of Adam.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

OBJ 2: Further, in every genus the principle is nobler than what is from
the principle. Hence, if He wished to assume human nature, He ought to
have assumed it in Adam himself.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

OBJ 3: Further, the Gentiles were greater sinners than the Jews, as a
gloss says on Gal. 2:15: "For we by nature are Jews, and not of the
Gentiles, sinners." Hence, if He wished to assume human nature from
sinners, He ought rather to have assumed it from the Gentiles than from
the stock of Abraham, who was just.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

On the contrary, (Lk. 3), the genealogy of our Lord is traced back to
Adam.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

I answer that, As Augustine says (De Trin. xiii, 18): "God was able to
assume human nature elsewhere than from the stock of Adam, who by his sin
had fettered the whole human race; yet God judged it better to assume
human nature from the vanquished race, and thus to vanquish the enemy of
the human race." And this for three reasons: First, because it would seem
to belong to justice that he who sinned should make amends; and hence
that from the nature which he had corrupted should be assumed that
whereby satisfaction was to be made for the whole nature. Secondly, it
pertains to man's greater dignity that the conqueror of the devil should
spring from the stock conquered by the devil. Thirdly, because God's
power is thereby made more manifest, since, from a corrupt and weakened
nature, He assumed that which was raised to such might and glory.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 1: Christ ought to be separated from sinners as regards sin,
which He came to overthrow, and not as regards nature which He came to
save, and in which "it behooved Him in all things to be made like to His
brethren," as the Apostle says (Heb. 2:17). And in this is His innocence
the more wonderful, seeing that though assumed from a mass tainted by
sin, His nature was endowed with such purity.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 2: As was said above (ad 1) it behooved Him Who came to take
away sins to be separated from sinners as regards sin, to which Adam was
subject, whom Christ "brought out of his sin," as is written (Wis. 10:2).
For it behooved Him Who came to cleanse all, not to need cleansing
Himself; just as in every genus of motion the first mover is immovable as
regards that motion, and the first to alter is itself unalterable. Hence
it was not fitting that He should assume human nature in Adam himself.

Aquin.: SMT TP Q[4] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

Reply OBJ 3: Since Christ ought especially to be separated from sinners
as regards sin, and to possess the highest innocence, it was fitting that
between the first sinner and Christ some just men should stand midway, in
whom certain forecasts of (His) future holiness should shine forth. And
hence, even in the people from whom Christ was to be born, God appointed
signs of holiness, which began in Abraham, who was the first to receive
the promise of Christ, and circumcision, as a sign that the covenant
should be kept, as is written (Gn. 17:11).





Previous - Next

Table of Contents | Words: Alphabetical - Frequency - Inverse - Length - Statistics | Help | IntraText Library

Best viewed with any browser at 800x600 or 768x1024 on Tablet PC
IntraText® (V89) - Some rights reserved by EuloTech SRL - 1996-2007. Content in this page is licensed under a Creative Commons License