V. THE SVETASVATARA-UPANISHAD.
THE Svetâsvatara-upanishad has been handed down as
one of the thirty-three Upanishads of the Taittirîyas, and though this has been
doubted, no real argument has ever been brought forward to invalidate the
tradition which represents it as belonging to the Taittirîya or Black
Yagur-veda.
It is sometimes called Svetâsvatarânâm Mantropanishad (p.
274), and is frequently spoken of in the plural, as Svetâsvataropanishadah. At
the end of the last Adhyâya we read that Svetâsvatara told it to the best among
the hermits, and that it should be kept secret, and not be taught to any one
except to a son or a regular pupil. It is also called Svetâsva [1], though, it
would seem, for the sake of the metre only. The Svetâsvataras are mentioned as
a Sâkha [2], subordinate to the Karakas; but of the literature belonging to
them in particular, nothing is ever mentioned beyond this Upanishad.
Svetâsvatara means a white mule, and as mules were known and
prized in India from the earliest times, Svetâsvatara, as the name of a person,
is no more startling than Svetâsva, white horse, an epithet of Arguna. Now as
no one would be likely to conclude from the name of one of the celebrated Vedic
Rishis, Syâvâsva, i.e. black horse, that negro influences might be discovered
in his hymns, it is hardly necessary to say that all speculations as to
Christian influences, or the teaching of white Syro-Christian missionaries,
being indicated by the name of Svetâsvatara, are groundless[3].
The Svetâsvatara-upanishad holds a very high rank among the
Upanishads. Though we cannot say that it is quoted by name by Bâdarâyana in the
Vedânta-sûtras,
[1. Vikaspatyam, p. 1222.
2. Catal. Bodl. p. 271 a; p.
222 a.
3 See Weber, Ind. Stud. I,
pp. 400, 421.]
it is distinctly referred to as sruta or revealed[1]. It is
one of the twelve Upanishads chosen by Vidyâranya in his
Sarvopanishad-arthânabhûitiprakâsa, and it was singled out by Sankara as worthy
of a special commentary.
The Svetâsvatara-upanishad seems to me one of the most
difficult, and at the same time one of the most interesting works of its kind.
Whether on that and on other grounds it should be assigned to a more ancient or
to a more modern period is what, in the present state of our knowledge, or, to
be honest, of our ignorance of minute chronology during the Vedic period, no true
scholar would venture to assert. We must be satisfied to know that, as a class,
the Upanishads are presupposed by the Kalpa-sûtras, that some of them, called
Mantra-upanishads, form part of the more modern Samhitâs, and that there are
portions even in the Rig-veda-samhitâs[2] for which the name of Upanishad is
claimed by the Anukramanîs. We find them most frequent, however, during the
Brâhmana-period, in the Brâhmanas themselves, and, more especially, in those
portions which are called Âranyakas, while a large number of them is referred
to the Atharva-veda. That, in imitation of older Upanishads, similar treatises
were composed to a comparatively recent time, has, of course, long been
known[3].
But when we approach the question whether among the ancient and
genuine Upanishads one may be older than the other, we find that, though we may
guess much, we can prove nothing. The Upanishads belonged to Parishads or
settlements spread all over India. There is a stock of ideas, even of
expressions, common to most of them. Yet, the ideas collected in the Upanishads
cannot all have grown tip in one and the same place, still less in regular
succession. They must have had an independent growth, determined by individual
and local influences, and opinions which in one village might seem far
advanced, would in another be looked upon as behind the world. We may
[1. See Deussen, Vedânta, p.
24;Ved. Sûtra I, 1, II; I, 4, 8; II, 3, 22.
2. See Sacred Books of the
East, vol. i, p. 1xvi.
3. Loc. cit. p. 1xvii.]
admire the ingeniousness of those who sometimes in this,
sometimes in that peculiarity see a clear indication of the modern date of an
Upanishad, but to a conscientious scholar such arguments are really distasteful
for the very sake of their ingeniousness. He knows that they will convince many
who do not know the real difficulties; he knows they will have to be got out of
the way with no small trouble, and he knows that, even if they should prove
true in the end, they will require very different support from what they have hitherto
received, before they can be admitted to the narrow circle of scientific facts.
While fully admitting therefore that the
Svetâsvatara-upanishad has its peculiar features and its peculiar difficulties,
I must most strongly maintain that no argument that has as yet been brought
forward, seems to me to prove, in any sense of the word, its modern character.
It has been said, for instance, that the
Svetâsvatara-upanishad is a sectarian Upanishad, because, when speaking of the
Highest Self or the Highest Brahman, it applies such names to him as Hara (I,
10), Rudra (II, 17; III, 2; 4; IV, 12; 21; 22), Siva (III, 14; IV, 10),
Bhagavat (III, 14), Agni, Âditya, Vâyu, &c. (IV, 2). But here it is simply
taken for granted that the idea of the Highest Self was developed first, and,
after it had reached its highest purity, was lowered again by an identification
with mythological and personal deities. The questions whether the conception of
the Highest Self was formed once and once only, whether it was formed after all
the personal and mythological deities had first been merged into one Lord
(Pragâpati), or whether it was discovered behind the veil of any other name in
the mythological pantheon of the past, have never been mooted. Why should not
an ancient Rishi have said: What we have hitherto called Rudra, and what we
worship as Agni, or Siva, is in reality the Highest Self, thus leaving much of
the ancient mythological phraseology to be used with a new meaning? Why should
we at once conclude that late sectarian worshippers of mythological gods
replaced again the Highest Self, after their fathers had discovered it, by
their own sectarian names? If we adopt the former view, the Upanishads, which
still show these rudera of the ancient temples, would have to be considered as
more primitive even than those in which the idea of the Brahman or the Highest
Self has reached its utmost purity.
It has been considered a very strong argument in support of
the modern and sectarian character of the Svetâsvatara-upanishad, that 'it inculcates
what is called Bhakti [1], or implicit reliance on the favour of the deity
worshipped.' Now it is quite true that this Upanishad possesses a very distinct
character of its own, by the stress which it lays on the personal, and
sometimes almost mythical character of the Supreme Spirit; but, so far from
inculcating bhakti, in the modern sense of the word, it never mentions that
word, except in the very last verse, a verse which, if necessary, certain
critics would soon dispose of as a palpable addition. But that verse says no
more than this: 'If these truths (of the Upanishad) have been told to a
high-minded man, who feels the highest devotion for God, and for his Guru as
for God, then they will shine forth indeed.' Does that prove the existence of Bhakti
as we find it in the Sândilya-sûtras[2]?
Again, it has been said that the Svetâsvatara-upanishad is
sectarian in a philosophical sense, that it is in fact an Upanishad of the
Sânkhya system of philosophy, and not of the Vedânta. Now I am quite willing to
admit that, in its origin, the Vedânta philosophy is nearer to the Vedic
literature than any other of the six systems of philosophy, and that if we
really found doctrines, peculiar to the Sânkhya, and opposed to the Vedânta, in
the Svetâsvataraupanishad, we might feel inclined to assign to our Upanishad a
later date. But where is the proof of this?
No doubt there are expressions in this Upanishad which
remind us of technical terms used at a later time in the Sânkhya system of
philosophy, but of Sânkhya doctrines, which I had myself formerly suspected in
this Upanishad,
[1. Weber, Ind. Stud. I, 422;
and History of Indian Literature, p. 238.
2. The Aphorisms of Sândilya,
or the Hindu Doctrine of Faith, translated by E. B. Cowell, Calcutta, 1879.]
I can on closer study find very little. I think it was Mr.
Gough who, in his Philosophy of the Upanishads, for the first time made it
quite clear that the teaching of our Upanishad is, in the main, the same as
that of the other Upanishads. 'The Svetâsvatara-upanishad teaches,' as he says,
'the unity of souls in the one and only Self; the unreality of the world as a
series of figments of the selffeigning world-fiction; and as the first of the
fictitious emanations, the existence of the Demiurgos or universal soul present
in every individual soul, the deity that projects the world out of himself,
that the migrating souls may find the recompense of their works in former
lives.'
I do not quite agree with this view of the Îsvara, whom Mr.
Gough calls the Dcmiurgos, but he seems to me perfectly right when he says that
the Swetâsvatara-upanishad propounds in Sânkhya terms the very principles that
the Sânkhya philosophers make it their business to subvert. One might doubt as
to the propriety of calling certain terms 'Sânkhya terms' in a work written at
a time when a Sânkhya philosophy, such as we know it as a system, had as yet no
existence, and when the very name Sânkhya meant something quite different from
the Sânkhya system of Kapila. Sânkhya is derived from sankhyâ, and that meant
counting, number, name, corresponding very nearly to the Greek [lógos].
Sânkhya, as derived from it, meant originally no more than theoretic
philosophy, as opposed to yoga, which meant originally practical religious
exercises and penances, to restrain the passions and the senses in general. All
other interpretations of these words, when they had become technical names, are
of later date.
But even in their later forms, whatever we may think of the
coincidences and differences between the Sânkhya and Vedânta systems of
philosophy, there is one point on which they are diametrically opposed.
Whatever else the Sânkhya may be, it is dualistic; whatever else the Vedânta
may be, it is monistic. In the Sânkhya, nature, or whatever else we may call
it, is independent of the purusha; in the Vedânta it is not. Now the
Svetâsvatara-upanishad states distinctly that nature, or what in the Sânkhya
philosophy is intended by Pradhâna, is not an independent power, but a power
(sakti) forming the very self of the Deva. 'Sages,' we read, 'devoted to
meditation and concentration, have seen the power belonging to God himself,
hidden in its own qualities.'
What is really peculiar in the Svetâsvatara-upanishad is the
strong stress which it lays on the personality of the Lord, the Îsvara, Deva,
in the passage quoted, is perhaps the nearest approach to our own idea of a
personal God, though without the background which the Vedânta always retains
for it. It is God as creator and ruler of the world, as îsvara, lord, but not
as Paramâtman, or the Highest Self. The Paramâtman constitutes, no doubt, his
real essence, but creation and creator have a phenomenal character only[1]. The
creation is mâyâ, in its original sense of work, then of phenomenal work, then
of illusion. The creator is mâyin, in its original sense of worker or maker,
but again, in that character, phenomenal only[2]. The Gunas or qualities arise,
according to the Vedânta, from prakriti or mâyâ, within, not beside, the
Highest Self, and this is the very idea which is here expressed by 'the
Self-power of God, hidden in the gunas or determining qualities.' How easily
that sakti or power may become an independent being, as Mâyâ, we see in such
verses as:
Sarvabhûteshu sarvâtman yâ saktir aparâbbavâ
Gunâsrayâ namas tasyai sasvatâyai paresvara [3].
But the important point is this, that in the
Svetâsvatara-upanishad this change has not taken place. Throughout the whole of
it we have one Being only, as the cause of everything, never two. Whatever
Sânkhya philosophers of a later date may have imagined that they could discover
in that Upanishad in support of their theories[4], there is not one passage in
it which, if rightly interpreted, not by itself, but in connection with the
whole text, could be quoted in
[1. Prathamam îsvarâtmanâ
mâyirûpenâvatishthate brahma; See p. 280, 1. 5.
2. Mâyî srigate sarvam etat.
3. See p. 279, 1. 5.
Sârvatman seems a vocative, like paresvara.
4. See Sarvadarsanasaiigraha,
p. 152.]
support of a dualistic philosophy such as the Sânkhya, as a
system, decidedly is.
If we want to understand, what seems at first sight
contradictory, the existence of a God, a Lord, a Creator, a Ruler, and at the
same time the existence of the super-personal Brahman, we must remember that
the orthodox view of the Vedânta[1] is not what we should call Evolution, but
Illusion. Evolution of the Brahman, or Parinâma, is heterodox, illusion or
Vivarta is orthodox Vedânta. Brahman is a concept involving such complete
perfection that with it evolution, or a tendency towards higher perfection, is
impossible. If therefore there is change, that change can only be illusion, and
can never claim the same reality as Brahman. To put it metaphorically, the
world, according to the orthodox Vedântin, does not proceed from Brahman as a
tree from a germ, but as a mirage from the rays of the sun. The world is, as we
express it, phenomenal only, but whatever objective reality there is in it, is
Brahman, 'das Ding an sich,' as Kant might call it.
Then what is Îsvara, or Deva, the Lord or God? The answers
given to this question are not very explicit. Historically, no doubt, the idea
of the Îsvara, the personal God, the creator and ruler, the omniscient and
omnipotent, existed before the idea of the absolute Brahman, and after the idea
of the Brahman had been elaborated, the difficulty of effecting a compromise
between the two ideas, had to be overcome. Îsvara, the Lord, is Brahman, for
what else could he be? But he is Brahman under a semblance, the semblance,
namely, of a personal creating and governing God. He is not created, but is the
creator, an office too low, it was supposed, for Brahman. The power which
enabled Îsvara to create, was a power within him, not independent of him,
whether we call it Devâtmasakti, Mâyâ, or Prakriti. That power is really
inconceivable, and it has assumed such different forms in the mind of different
Vedântists, that in the end Mâyâ herself is represented as the creating power,
nay, as having created Îsvara himself.
[1. Vedantaparibhâshâ, in the
Pandit, vol. iv, p. 496.]
In our Upanishad, however, Îsvara is the creator, and
though, philosophically speaking, we should say that be was conceived as
phenomenal, yet we must never forget that the phenomenal is the form of the
real, and Îsvara therefore an aspect of Brahman[1]. 'This God,' says Pramâda
Dâsa Mitra[2], 'is the spirit conscious of the universe. Whilst an extremely
limited portion, and that only of the material universe, enters into my
consciousness, the whole of the conscious universe, together, of course, with
the material one that hangs upon it, enters into the consciousness of God.' And
again, 'Whilst we (the gîvâtmans) are subject to Mâyâ, Mâyâ is subject to
Îsvara. If we truly know Îsvara, we know him as Brahman; if we truly know
ourselves, we know ourselves as Brahman. This being so, we must not be
surprised if sometimes we find Îsvara sharply distinguished from Brahman,
whilst at other times Îsvara, and Brahman are interchanged.'
Another argument in support of the sectarian character of
the Svetâsvatara-upanishad is brought forward, not by European students only,
but by native scholars, namely, that the very name of Kapila, the reputed
founder of the Sânkhya philosophy, occurs in it. Now it is quite true that if
we read the second verse of the fifth Adhyâya by itself, the occurrence of the
word Kapila may seem startling. But if we read it in connection with what
precedes and follows, we shall see hardly anything unusual in it. It says:
'It is he who, being one only, rules over every germ
(cause), over all forms, and over all germs; it is he who, in the beginning,
bears in his thoughts the wise son, the fiery, whom he wished to look on while
he was born.'
Now it is quite clear to me that the subject in this verse
is the same as in IV, II, where the same words are used, and where yo yonim
yonim adhitishthaty ekah refers clearly to Brahman. It is equally clear that
the prasûta, the son, the offspring of Brahman, in the Vedânta sense, can only
be the same person who is elsewhere called Hiranyagarbha,
[1. Savisesham Brahma, or
sabalam Brahma.
2. Journal of the Royal
Asiatic Society, 1878, p. 40.]
the personified Brahman. Thus we read before, III, 4, 'He
the creator and supporter of the gods, Rudra, the great seer (maharshi), the
lord of all, formerly gave birth to Hiranyagarbha;' and in IV, 11, we have the
very expression which is used here, namely, 'that he saw Hiranyagarbha being
born.' Unfortunately, a new adjective is applied in our verse to Hiranyagarbha,
namely, kapila, and this has called forth interpretations totally at variance
with the general tenor of the Upanishad. If, instead of kapilam, reddish,
fiery[1], any other epithet had been used of Hiranyagarbha, no one, I believe,
would have hesitated for a moment to recognise the fact that our text simply
repeats the description of Hiranyagarbha in his relation to Brahman, for the
other epithet rishim, like maharshim, is too often applied to Brahman himself
and to Hiranyagarbha to require any explanation.
But it is a well known fact that the Hindus, even as early
as the Brâhmana-period, were fond of tracing their various branches of
knowledge back to Brahman or to Brahman Svayambhû and then through Pragâpati,
who even in the Rig-veda (X, 121, 10) replaces Hiranyagarbha, and sometimes
through the Devas, such as Mrityu, Vâyu, Indra, Agni [2], &c., to the
various ancestors of their ancient families.
In the beginning of the Mundakopanishad we are told that
Brahman told it to Atharvan, Atharvan to Angir, Angir to Satyavâha Bhâradvâga,
Bhâradvâga to Angiras, Angiras to Saunaka. Manu, the ancient lawgiver, is
called both Hairanyagarbha and Svâyambhuva, as descended from Svâyambhu or from
Hiranyagarbha [3]. Nothing therefore was more natural than that the same
tendency should have led some one to assign the authorship of a great
philosophical system like the Sankhya to Hiranyagarbha, if not to Brahman
Svayambhû. And if the name of Hiranyagarbha had been used already for the
ancestors of other sages, and the inspirers of other systems, what could be
more natural than that another name of the same Hiranyagarbha
[1. Other colours, instead of
kapila, are nîla, harita, lohitâksha; see IV, 1; 4.
See Vamsa-brâhmana, ed.
Burnell, p. io; Brihadâranyaka-up. pp, 185, 224.
3 See M. M., India, p. 372.]
should be chosen, such as Kapila. If we are told that Kapila
handed his knowledge to Asuri, Asuri to Pañkasikha, this again is in perfect
keeping with the character of literary tradition in India. Asuri occurs in the
Vamsas ofthe Satapatha-brâhmana (see above, pp. 187, 2-6); Pañkasikha[1],
having five tufts, might be either a general name or a proper name of an
ascetic, Buddhist or otherwise. He is quoted in the Sânkhya-sûtras, V, 32; VI,
68.
But after all this was settled, after Kapila had been
accepted, like Hiranyagarbha, as the founder of a great system of philosophy,
there came a reaction. People had now learnt to believe in a real Kapila, and
when looking out for credentials for him, they found them wherever the word
Kapila occurred in old writings. The question whether there ever was a real
historical person who took the name of Kapila and taught the Sânkhya-sûtras,
does not concern us here. I see no evidence for it. What is instructive is
this, that our very passage, which may have suggested at first the name of
Kapila, as distinct from Hiranyagarbha, Kapila, was later on appealed to to
prove the primordial existence of a Kapila, the founder of the Sânkhya
philosophy. However, it requires but a very slight acquaintance with Sanskrit
literature and very little reflection in order to see that the author of our
verse could never have dreamt of elevating a certain Kapila, known to him as a
great philosopher, if there ever was such a man, to a divine rank[2].
Hiranyagarbha kapila may have given birth to Kapila, the hero of the Sânkhya
philosophers, but Kapila, a real human person, was never changed into
Hiranyagarbha kapila.
Let us see now what the commentators say. Sankara first
explains kapilam by kanakam [3] kapilavarnam . . . . Hiranyagarbham. Kapilo
'graga iti purânavakanât. Kapilo Hiranyagarbho vâ nirdisyate. But he afterwards
quotes some verses in support of the theory that Kapila was a
[1. For fuller information on
Pañkasikha, Kapila, &c., see F. Hall's Preface to Sânkhya-pravakana-bhâshya,
p. 9 seq.; Weber, Ind. Stud. I, p. 433.
2. Weber, Hist. of Indian
Literature, p. 236.
3. This ought to be
Kanakavarnam, and I hope will not be identified with the name of Buddha in a
former existence.]
Paramarshi, a portion of Vishnu, intended to destroy error
in the Krita Yuga, a teacher of the Sânkhya philosophy.
Vigñânâtman explains the verse rightly, and without any
reference to Kapila, the Sânkhya teacher.
Safikarânanda goes a step further, and being evidently fully
aware of the misuse that had been made of this passage, even in certain
passages of the Mahâbhârata (XII, 13254, 13703), and elsewhere, declares
distinctly that kapila cannot be meant for the teacher of the Sânkhya (na tu
sânkhyapranetâ kapilah, nâmamâtrasâmyena tadgrahane syâd atiprasangah). He is
fully aware of the true interpretation, viz. avyâkritasya prathamakâryabhûtam
kapilam vikitravarnam gñânakriyâsaktyâtmakam Hiranyagarbham ityarthah, but he
yields to another temptation, and seems to prefer another view which makes
Kapila Vâsudevasyâvatârabûtam Sagaraputrânâm dagdhâram, an Avatâra of Vâsudeva,
the burner of the sons of Sagara. What vast conclusions may be drawn from no
facts, may be seen in Weber's Indische Studien, vol. i, p. 430, and even in his
History of Indian Literature, published in 1878.
Far more difficult to explain than these supposed allusions
to the authors and to the teaching of the Sânkhya philosophy are the frequent
references in the Svetâsvatara-upanishad to definite numbers, which are
supposed to point to certain classes of subjects as arranged in the Sânkhya and
other systems of philosophy. The Sânkhya philosophy is fond of counting and
arranging, and its very name is sometimes supposed to have been chosen because
it numbers (sankhyâ) the subjects of which it treats. It is certainly true that
if we meet, as we do in the Svetâsvatara-upanishad, with classes of things',
numbered as one, two, three, five, eight, sixteen, twenty, forty-eight, fifty
and more, and if some of these numbers agree with those recognised in the later
Sânkhya and Yoga systems, we feel doubtful as to whether these coincidences are
accidental, or whether, if not accidental, they are due to borrowing on the
part of those later systems, or on the part
[1. See I, 4; 5; VI, 3]
it impossible to come to a decision on this point. Even so
early as the hymns of the Rig-veda we meet with these numbers assigned to days
and months and seasons, rivers and countries, sacrifices and deities. They
clearly prove the existence of a considerable amount of intellectual labour
which had become fixed and traditional before the composition of certain hymns,
and they prove the same in the case of certain Upanishads. But beyond this, for
the present, I should not like to go; and I must say that the attempts of most
of the Indian commentators at explaining such numbers bya reference to later
systems of philosophy or cosmology, are generally very forced and
unsatisfactory.
One more point I ought to mention as indicating the age of
the Svetâsvatara-upanishad, and that is the obscurity of many of its verses,
which may be due to a corruption of the text, and the number of various
readings, recognised as such, by the commentators. Some of them have been
mentioned in the notes to my translation.
The text of this Upanishad was printed by Dr. Roer in the
Bibliotheca Indica, with Sankara's commentary. I have consulted besides, the
commentary of Vigñânâtman, the pupil of
Paramahamsa-parivrâgakâkârya-srîmag-Gñânotta- mâkârya, MS. I. O. 1133; and a
third commentary, by Sahkarânanda, the pupil of
Paramahamsa-parivrâgakâkâryânandâtman, MS. I. O. 1878. These were kindly lent
me by Dr. Rost, the learned and liberal librarian of the India
Office.
|