"We must obey God rather than
men" (Acts 5:29):
civil law and the moral law
68. One of the specific
characteristics of present-day attacks on human life - as has already been said
several times - consists in the trend to demand a legal justification for them,
as if they were rights which the State, at least under certain conditions, must
acknowledge as belonging to citizens. Consequently, there is a tendency to
claim that it should be possible to exercise these rights with the safe and
free assistance of doctors and medical personnel.
It is often claimed that the life of an unborn child
or a seriously disabled person is only a relative good: according to a
proportionalist approach, or one of sheer calculation, this good should be
compared with and balanced against other goods. It is even maintained that only
someone present and personally involved in a concrete situation can correctly
judge the goods at stake: consequently, only that person would be able to
decide on the morality of his choice. The State therefore, in the interest of
civil coexistence and social harmony, should respect this choice, even to the
point of permitting abortion and euthanasia.
At other times, it is claimed that civil law cannot
demand that all citizens should live according to moral standards higher than
what all citizens themselves acknowledge and share. Hence the law should always
express the opinion and will of the majority of citizens and recognize that
they have, at least in certain extreme cases, the right even to abortion and euthanasia.
Moreover the prohibition and the punishment of abortion and euthanasia in these
cases would inevitably lead - so it is said - to an increase of illegal
practices: and these would not be subject to necessary control by society and
would be carried out in a medically unsafe way. The question is also raised
whether supporting a law which in practice cannot be enforced would not
ultimately undermine the authority of all laws.
Finally, the more radical views go so far as to
maintain that in a modern and pluralistic society people should be allowed
complete freedom to dispose of their own lives as well as of the lives of the
unborn: it is asserted that it is not the task of the law to choose between
different moral opinions, and still less can the law claim to impose one
particular opinion to the detriment of others.
69. In any case, in the democratic
culture of our time it is commonly held that the legal system of any society
should limit itself to taking account of and accepting the convictions of the
majority. It should therefore be based solely upon what the majority itself
considers moral and actually practises. Furthermore, if it is believed that an
objective truth shared by all is de facto unattainable, then respect for the
freedom of the citizens - who in a democratic system are considered the true
rulers - would require that on the legislative level the autonomy of individual
consciences be acknowledged. Consequently, when establishing those norms which
are absolutely necessary for social coexistence, the only determining factor
should be the will of the majority, whatever this may be. Hence every
politician, in his or her activity, should clearly separate the realm of
private conscience from that of public conduct.
As a result we have what appear to be two
diametrically opposed tendencies. On the one hand, individuals claim for
themselves in the moral sphere the most complete freedom of choice and demand
that the State should not adopt or impose any ethical position but limit itself
to guaranteeing maximum space for the freedom of each individual, with the sole
limitation of not infringing on the freedom and rights of any other citizen. On
the other hand, it is held that, in the exercise of public and professional
duties, respect for other people's freedom of choice requires that each one
should set aside his or her own convictions in order to satisfy every demand of
the citizens which is recognized and guaranteed by law; in carrying out one's
duties the only moral criterion should be what is laid down by the law itself.
Individual responsibility is thus turned over to the civil law, with a
renouncing of personal conscience, at least in the public sphere.
70. At the basis of all these
tendencies lies the ethical relativism which characterizes much of present-day
culture. There are those who consider such relativism an essential condition of
democracy, inasmuch as it alone is held to guarantee tolerance, mutual respect
between people and acceptance of the decisions of the majority, whereas moral
norms considered to be objective and binding are held to lead to
authoritarianism and intolerance.
But it is precisely the issue of respect for life
which shows what misunderstandings and contradictions, accompanied by terrible
practical consequences, are concealed in this position.
It is true that history has known cases where crimes
have been committed in the name of "truth". But equally grave crimes
and radical denials of freedom have also been committed and are still being
committed in the name of "ethical relativism". When a parliamentary
or social majority decrees that it is legal, at least under certain conditions,
to kill unborn human life, is it not really making a "tyrannical"
decision with regard to the weakest and most defenceless of human beings?
Everyone's conscience rightly rejects those crimes against humanity of which
our century has had such sad experience. But would these crimes cease to be
crimes if, instead of being committed by unscrupulous tyrants, they were
legitimated by popular consensus?
Democracy cannot be idolized to the point of making it
a substitute for morality or a panacea for immorality. Fundamentally, democracy
is a "system" and as such is a means and not an end. Its
"moral" value is not automatic, but depends on conformity to the
moral law to which it, like every other form of human behaviour, must be
subject: in other words, its morality depends on the morality of the ends which
it pursues and of the means which it employs. If today we see an almost
universal consensus with regard to the value of democracy, this is to be
considered a positive "sign of the times", as the Church's
Magisterium has frequently noted.
88 But the value of democracy stands or falls with the
values which it embodies and promotes. Of course, values such as the dignity of
every human person, respect for inviolable and inalienable human rights, and
the adoption of the "common good" as the end and criterion regulating
political life are certainly fundamental and not to be ignored.
The basis of these values cannot be provisional and
changeable "majority" opinions, but only the acknowledgment of an
objective moral law which, as the "natural law" written in the human
heart, is the obligatory point of reference for civil law itself. If, as a
result of a tragic obscuring of the collective conscience, an attitude of
scepticism were to succeed in bringing into question even the fundamental
principles of the moral law, the democratic system itself would be shaken in
its foundations, and would be reduced to a mere mechanism for regulating
different and opposing interests on a purely empirical basis. 89
Some might think that even this function, in the
absence of anything better, should be valued for the sake of peace in society.
While one acknowledges some element of truth in this point of view, it is easy
to see that without an objective moral grounding not even democracy is capable
of ensuring a stable peace, especially since peace which is not built upon the
values of the dignity of every individual and of solidarity between all people
frequently proves to be illusory. Even in participatory systems of government,
the regulation of interests often occurs to the advantage of the most powerful,
since they are the ones most capable of manoeuvering not only the levers of
power but also of shaping the formation of consensus. In such a situation,
democracy easily becomes an empty word.
71. It is therefore urgently
necessary, for the future of society and the development of a sound democracy,
to rediscover those essential and innate human and moral values which flow from
the very truth of the human being and express and safeguard the dignity of the
person: values which no individual, no majority and no State can ever create,
modify or destroy, but must only acknowledge, respect and promote.
Consequently there is a need to recover the basic
elements of a vision of the relationship between civil law and moral law, which
are put forward by the Church, but which are also part of the patrimony of the
great juridical traditions of humanity.
Certainly the purpose of civil law is different and
more limited in scope than that of the moral law. But "in no sphere of
life can the civil law take the place of conscience or dictate norms concerning
things which are outside its competence",90 which is that of
ensuring the common good of people through the recognition and defence of their
fundamental rights, and the promotion of peace and of public morality. 91
The real purpose of civil law is to guarantee an ordered social coexistence in
true justice, so that all may "lead a quiet and peaceable life, godly and
respectful in every way" (1 Tim 2:2).
Precisely for this reason, civil law must ensure that all members of society
enjoy respect for certain fundamental rights which innately belong to the
person, rights which every positive law must recognize and guarantee. First and
fundamental among these is the inviolable right to life of every innocent human
being. While public authority can sometimes choose not to put a stop to
something which - were it prohibited - would cause more serious harm,
92 it can never presume to legitimize as a right of individuals - even
if they are the majority of the members of society - an offence against other
persons caused by the disregard of so fundamental a right as the right to life.
The legal toleration of abortion or of euthanasia can in no way claim to be
based on respect for the conscience of others, precisely because society has
the right and the duty to protect itself against the abuses which can occur in
the name of conscience and under the pretext of freedom. 93
In the Encyclical Pacem in Terris, John XXIII pointed
out that "it is generally accepted today that the common good is best
safeguarded when personal rights and duties are guaranteed. The chief concern
of civil authorities must therefore be to ensure that these rights are
recognized, respected, coordinated, defended and promoted, and that each
individual is enabled to perform his duties more easily. For ?to safeguard the
inviolable rights of the human person, and to facilitate the performance of his
duties, is the principal duty of every public authority'. Thus any government
which refused to recognize human rights or acted in violation of them, would
not only fail in its duty; its decrees would be wholly lacking in binding
force".94
72. The doctrine on the necessary
conformity of civil law with the moral law is in continuity with the whole
tradition of the Church. This is clear once more from John XXIII's Encyclical:
"Authority is a postulate of the moral order and derives from God.
Consequently, laws and decrees enacted in contravention of the moral order, and
hence of the divine will, can have no binding force in conscience...; indeed,
the passing of such laws undermines the very nature of authority and results in
shameful abuse".95 This is the clear teaching of Saint Thomas Aquinas,
who writes that "human law is law inasmuch as it is in conformity with
right reason and thus derives from the eternal law. But when a law is contrary
to reason, it is called an unjust law; but in this case it ceases to be a law
and becomes instead an act of violence".96 And again: "Every
law made by man can be called a law insofar as it derives from the natural law.
But if it is somehow opposed to the natural law, then it is not really a law
but rather a corruption of the law".97
Now the first and most immediate application of this
teaching concerns a human law which disregards the fundamental right and source
of all other rights which is the right to life, a right belonging to every
individual. Consequently, laws which legitimize the direct killing of innocent
human beings through abortion or euthanasia are in complete opposition to the
inviolable right to life proper to every individual; they thus deny the
equality of everyone before the law. It might be objected that such is not the
case in euthanasia, when it is requested with full awareness by the person
involved. But any State which made such a request legitimate and authorized it
to be carried out would be legalizing a case of suicide-murder, contrary to the
fundamental principles of absolute respect for life and of the protection of
every innocent life. In this way the State contributes to lessening respect for
life and opens the door to ways of acting which are destructive of trust in
relations between people. Laws which authorize and promote abortion and
euthanasia are therefore radically opposed not only to the good of the
individual but also to the common good; as such they are completely lacking in
authentic juridical validity. Disregard for the right to life, precisely
because it leads to the killing of the person whom society exists to serve, is
what most directly conflicts with the possibility of achieving the common good.
Consequently, a civil law authorizing abortion or euthanasia ceases by that
very fact to be a true, morally binding civil law.
73. Abortion and euthanasia are thus
crimes which no human law can claim to legitimize. There is no obligation in
conscience to obey such laws; instead there is a grave and clear obligation to oppose
them by conscientious objection. From the very beginnings of the Church, the
apostolic preaching reminded Christians of their duty to obey legitimately
constituted public authorities (cf. Rom
13:1-7; 1 Pet 2:13-14), but at
the same time it firmly warned that "we must obey God rather than
men" (Acts 5:29). In the Old
Testament, precisely in regard to threats against life, we find a significant
example of resistance to the unjust command of those in authority. After
Pharaoh ordered the killing of all newborn males, the Hebrew midwives refused.
"They did not do as the king of Egypt commanded them, but let the
male children live" (Ex 1:17). But
the ultimate reason for their action should be noted: "the midwives feared
God" (ibid.). It is precisely from
obedience to God - to whom alone is due that fear which is acknowledgment of
his absolute sovereignty - that the strength and the courage to resist unjust
human laws are born. It is the strength and the courage of those prepared even
to be imprisoned or put to the sword, in the certainty that this is what makes
for "the endurance and faith of the saints"
(Rev 13:10).
In the case of an intrinsically unjust law, such as a
law permitting abortion or euthanasia, it is therefore never licit to obey it,
or to "take part in a propaganda campaign in favour of such a law, or vote
for it".98
A particular problem of conscience can arise in cases
where a legislative vote would be decisive for the passage of a more
restrictive law, aimed at limiting the number of authorized abortions, in place
of a more permissive law already passed or ready to be voted on. Such cases are
not infrequent. It is a fact that while in some parts of the world there
continue to be campaigns to introduce laws favouring abortion, often supported
by powerful international organizations, in other nations - particularly those
which have already experienced the bitter fruits of such permissive legislation
- there are growing signs of a rethinking in this matter. In a case like the
one just mentioned, when it is not possible to overturn or completely abrogate
a pro-abortion law, an elected official, whose absolute personal opposition to
procured abortion was well known, could licitly support proposals aimed at
limiting the harm done by such a law and at lessening its negative consequences
at the level of general opinion and public morality. This does not in fact
represent an illicit cooperation with an unjust law, but rather a legitimate
and proper attempt to limit its evil aspects.
74. The passing of unjust laws often
raises difficult problems of conscience for morally upright people with regard
to the issue of cooperation, since they have a right to demand not to be forced
to take part in morally evil actions. Sometimes the choices which have to be
made are difficult; they may require the sacrifice of prestigious professional
positions or the relinquishing of reasonable hopes of career advancement. In
other cases, it can happen that carrying out certain actions, which are
provided for by legislation that overall is unjust, but which in themselves are
indifferent, or even positive, can serve to protect human lives under threat.
There may be reason to fear, however, that willingness to carry out such
actions will not only cause scandal and weaken the necessary opposition to
attacks on life, but will gradually lead to further capitulation to a mentality
of permissiveness.
In order to shed light on this difficult question, it
is necessary to recall the general principles concerning cooperation in evil
actions. Christians, like all people of good will, are called upon under grave
obligation of conscience not to cooperate formally in practices which, even if
permitted by civil legislation, are contrary to God's law. Indeed, from the
moral standpoint, it is never licit to cooperate formally in evil. Such
cooperation occurs when an action, either by its very nature or by the form it
takes in a concrete situation, can be defined as a direct participation in an
act against innocent human life or a sharing in the immoral intention of the
person committing it. This cooperation can never be justified either by
invoking respect for the freedom of others or by appealing to the fact that
civil law permits it or requires it. Each individual in fact has moral
responsibility for the acts which he personally performs; no one can be
exempted from this responsibility, and on the basis of it everyone will be
judged by God himself (cf. Rom 2:6;
14:12).
To refuse to take part in committing an injustice is
not only a moral duty; it is also a basic human right. Were this not so, the
human person would be forced to perform an action intrinsically incompatible
with human dignity, and in this way human freedom itself, the authentic meaning
and purpose of which are found in its orientation to the true and the good,
would be radically compromised. What is at stake therefore is an essential
right which, precisely as such, should be acknowledged and protected by civil
law. In this sense, the opportunity to refuse to take part in the phases of
consultation, preparation and execution of these acts against life should be
guaranteed to physicians, health-care personnel, and directors of hospitals,
clinics and convalescent facilities. Those who have recourse to conscientious
objection must be protected not only from legal penalties but also from any
negative effects on the legal, disciplinary, financial and professional plane.
|