14. Work and
Ownership
The historical process
briefly presented here has certainly gone beyond its initial phase, but it is
still taking place and indeed is spreading in the relationships between nations
and continents. It needs to be specified further from another point of view. It
is obvious that, when we speak of opposition between labour and capital, we are
not dealing only with abstract concepts or "impersonal forces"
operating in economic production. Behind both concepts there are people,
living, actual people: on the one side are those who do the work without being
the owners of the means of production, and on the other side those who act as
entrepreneurs and who own these means or represent the owners. Thus the
issue of ownership or property enters from the beginning into the whole of
this difficult historical process. The Encyclical Rerum
Novarum, which has the social question as its
theme, stresses this issue also, recalling and confirming the Church's teaching
on ownership, on the right to private property even when it is a question of
the means of production. The Encyclical Mater et Magistra did the same.
The above principle, as it
was then stated and as it is still taught by the Church, diverges radically
from the programme of collectivism as proclaimed by Marxism and put into
pratice in various countries in the decades following
the time of Leo XIII's Encyclical. At the same time
it differs from the programme of capitalism practised by liberalism and
by the political systems inspired by it. In the latter case, the difference
consists in the way the right to ownership or property is understood. Christian
tradition has never upheld this right as absolute and untouchable. On the
contrary, it has always understood this right within the broader context of the
right common to all to use the goods of the whole of creation: the right to
private property is subordinated to the right to common use, to the fact
that goods are meant for everyone.
Furthermore, in the
Church's teaching, ownership has never been understood in a way that could
constitute grounds for social conflict in labour. As mentioned above, property
is acquired first of all through work in order that it may serve work. This concerns in a special way ownership of the means of
production. Isolating these means as a separate property in order to set it up
in the form of "capital" in opposition to "labour"-and even
to practise exploitation of labour - is contrary to the very nature of these
means and their possession. They cannot be possessed against labour, they
cannot even be possessed for possession's sake, because the only
legitimate title to their possession - whether in the form of private ownerhip or in the form of public or collective ownership -
is that they should serve labour, and thus, by serving labour, that they
should make possible the achievement of the first principle of this order,
namely, the universal destination of goods and the right to common use of them.
From this point of view, therefore, in consideration of human labour and of
common access to the goods meant for man, one cannot exclude the socialization,
in suitable conditions, of certain means of production. In the course of
the decades since the publication of the Encyclical Rerum
Novarum, the Church's teaching has always
recalled all these principles, going back to the arguments formulated in a much
older tradition, for example, the well-known arguments of the Summa Theologiae of Saint Thomas Aquinas22.
In the present document,
which has human work as its main theme, it is right to confirm all the effort
with which the Church's teaching has striven and continues to strive always to
ensure the priority of work and, thereby, man's character as a subject in
social life and, especially, in the dynamic structure of the whole economic
process. From this point of view the position of "rigid"
capitalism continues to remain unacceptable, namely the position that defends
the exclusive right to private ownership of the means of production as an
untouchable "dogma" of economic life. The principle of respect for
work demands that this right should undergo a constructive revision, both in
theory and in practice. If it is true that capital, as the whole of the means
of production, is at the same time the product of the work of generations, it
is equally true that capital is being unceasingly created through the work done
with the help of all these means of production, and these means can be seen as
a great workbench at which the present generation of workers is working day
after day. Obviously we are dealing here with different kinds of work, not only
so-called manual labour but also the many forms of intellectual work, including
white-collar work and management.
In the light of the above,
the many proposals put forward by experts in Catholic social teaching and by
the highest Magisterium of the Church take on special
significance23: proposals for joint
ownership of the means of work, sharing by the workers in the management
and/or profits of businesses, so-called shareholding by labour, etc. Whether
these various proposals can or cannot be applied concretely, it is clear that
recognition of the proper position of labour and the worker in the production
process demands various adaptations in the sphere of the right to ownership of
the means of production. This is so not only in view of older situations but
also, first and foremost, in view of the whole of the situation and the problems
in the second half of the present century with regard to the so-called Third
World and the various new independent countries that have arisen, especially in
Africa but elsewhere as well, in place of the colonial territories of the past.
Therefore, while the
position of "rigid" capitalism must undergo continual revision, in
order to be reformed from the point of view of human rights, both human rights
in the widest sense and those linked with man's work, it must be stated that,
from the same point of view, these many deeply desired reforms cannot be
achieved by an a priori elimination of private ownership of the means of
production. For it must be noted that merely taking these means of
production (capital) out of the hands of their private owners is not enough to
ensure their satisfactory socialization. They cease to be the property of a
certain social group, namely the private owners, and become the property of
organized society, coming under the administration and direct control of
another group of people, namely those who, though not owning them, from the
fact of exercising power in society manage them on the level of the
whole national or the local economy.
This group in authority may
carry out its task satisfactorily from the point of view of the priority of
labour; but it may also carry it out badly by claiming for itself a monopoly
of the administration and disposal of the means of production and not
refraining even from offending basic human rights. Thus, merely converting the
means of production into State property in the collectivist system is by no
means equivalent to "socializing" that property. We can speak of
socializing only when the subject character of society is ensured, that is to
say, when on the basis of his work each person is fully entitled to consider
himself a part-owner of the great workbench at which he is working with every
one else. A way towards that goal could be found by associating labour with the
ownership of capital, as far as possible, and by producing a wide range of
intermediate bodies with economic, social and cultural purposes; they would be
bodies enjoying real autonomy with regard to the public powers, pursuing their
specific aims in honest collaboration with each other and in subordination to
the demands of the common good, and they would be living communities both in
form and in substance, in the sense that the members of each body would be
looked upon and treated as persons and encouraged to take an active part in the
life of the body24.
|