III. Fundamental choice
and specific kinds of behaviour
"Only do not use
your freedom as an opportunity for the flesh" (Gal 5:13)
65.
The heightened concern for freedom in our own day has led many students of the
behavioural and the theological sciences to develop a more penetrating analysis
of its nature and of its dynamics. It has been rightly pointed out that freedom
is not only the choice for one or another particular action; it is also, within
that choice, a decision about oneself and a setting of one's own life
for or against the Good, for or against the Truth, and ultimately for or
against God. Emphasis has rightly been placed on the importance of certain choices
which "shape" a person's entire moral life, and which serve as bounds
within which other particular everyday choices can be situated and allowed to
develop.
Some authors, however, have
proposed an even more radical revision of the relationship between person
and acts. They speak of a "fundamental freedom", deeper than and
different from freedom of choice, which needs to be considered if human actions
are to be correctly understood and evaluated. According to these authors, the key
role in the moral life is to be attributed to a "fundamental
option", brought about by that fundamental freedom whereby the person
makes an overall self-determination, not through a specific and conscious
decision on the level of reflection, but in a "transcendental" and
"athematic" way. Particular acts which
flow from this option would constitute only partial and never definitive
attempts to give it expression; they would only be its "signs" or
symptoms. The immediate object of such acts would not be absolute Good (before which
the freedom of the person would be expressed on a transcendental level), but
particular (also termed "categorical" ) goods. In the opinion of some
theologians, none of these goods, which by their nature are partial, could
determine the freedom of man as a person in his totality, even though it is
only by bringing them about or refusing to do so that man is able to express
his own fundamental option.
A distinction thus
comes to be introduced between the fundamental option and deliberate choices
of a concrete kind of behaviour. In some authors this division tends to
become a separation, when they expressly limit moral "good"
and "evil" to the transcendental dimension proper to the fundamental
option, and describe as "right" or "wrong" the choices of
particular "innerworldly" kinds of
behaviour: those, in other words, concerning man's relationship with himself,
with others and with the material world. There thus appears to be established
within human acting a clear disjunction between two levels of morality: on the
one hand the order of good and evil, which is dependent on the will, and on the
other hand specific kinds of behaviour, which are judged to be morally right or
wrong only on the basis of a technical calculation of the proportion between
the "premoral" or "physical"
goods and evils which actually result from the action. This is pushed to the
point where a concrete kind of behaviour, even one freely chosen, comes to be
considered as a merely physical process, and not according to the criteria
proper to a human act. The conclusion to which this eventually leads is that
the properly moral assessment of the person is reserved to his fundamental
option, prescinding in whole or in part from his
choice of particular actions, of concrete kinds of behaviour.
66.
There is no doubt that Christian moral teaching, even in its Biblical roots,
acknowledges the specific importance of a fundamental choice which qualifies
the moral life and engages freedom on a radical level before God. It is a question
of the decision of faith, of the obedience of faith (cf
Rom 16:26)
"by which man makes a total and free self-commitment to God, offering 'the
full submission of intellect and will to God as he reveals' ".112
This faith, which works through love (cf
Gal 5:6), comes from the core of man, from
his "heart" (cf Rom
10:10), whence it is called to bear fruit in works (cf Mt 12:33-35;
Lk
6:43-45; Rom 8:5-10; Gal
5:22). In the Decalogue one finds, as an introduction to the various
commandments, the basic clause: "I am the Lord your God..."
(Ex 20:2), which, by impressing
upon the numerous and varied particular prescriptions their primordial meaning,
gives the morality of the Covenant its aspect of completeness, unity and
profundity. Israel's
fundamental decision, then, is about the fundamental commandment (cf Jos
24:14-25; Ex 19:3-8;
Mic 6:8). The
morality of the New Covenant is similarly dominated by the fundamental call of
Jesus to follow him — thus he also says to the young man: "If you wish to
be perfect... then come, follow me" (Mt 19:21); to this call the
disciple must respond with a radical decision and choice. The Gospel parables
of the treasure and the pearl of great price, for which one sells all one's
possessions, are eloquent and effective images of the radical and unconditional
nature of the decision demanded by the Kingdom of God. The radical nature of
the decision to follow Jesus is admirably expressed in his own words:
"Whoever would save his life will lose it; and whoever loses his life for
my sake and the Gospel's will save it" (Mk
8:35).
Jesus' call to "come,
follow me" marks the greatest possible exaltation of human freedom, yet at
the same time it witnesses to the truth and to the obligation of acts of faith
and of decisions which can be described as involving a fundamental option. We
find a similar exaltation of human freedom in the words of Saint Paul: "You were called to freedom,
brethren" (Gal 5:13). But the Apostle immediately adds a grave
warning: "Only do not use your freedom as an opportunity for the
flesh". This warning echoes his earlier words: "For freedom Christ
has set us free; stand fast therefore, and do not submit again to a yoke of
slavery" (Gal 5:1). Paul encourages us
to be watchful, because freedom is always threatened by slavery. And this is
precisely the case when an act of faith — in the sense of a fundamental option
— becomes separated from the choice of particular acts, as in the tendencies
mentioned above.
67.
These tendencies are therefore contrary to the teaching of Scripture itself,
which sees the fundamental option as a genuine choice of freedom and links that
choice profoundly to particular acts. By his fundamental choice, man is capable
of giving his life direction and of progressing, with the help of grace,
towards his end, following God's call. But this capacity is actually exercised
in the particular choices of specific actions, through which man deliberately
conforms himself to God's will, wisdom and law. It thus needs to be stated that
the so-called fundamental option, to the extent that it is distinct from a
generic intention and hence one not yet determined in such a way that
freedom is obligated, is always brought into play through conscious and free
decisions. Precisely for this reason, it is revoked when man engages his
freedom in conscious decisions to the contrary, with regard to morally grave
matter.
To separate the fundamental
option from concrete kinds of behaviour means to contradict the substantial
integrity or personal unity of the moral agent in his body and in his soul. A
fundamental option understood without explicit consideration of the
potentialities which it puts into effect and the determinations which express
it does not do justice to the rational finality immanent in man's acting and in
each of his deliberate decisions. In point of fact, the morality of human acts
is not deduced only from one's intention, orientation or fundamental option,
understood as an intention devoid of a clearly determined binding content or as
an intention with no corresponding positive effort to fulfil the different
obligations of the moral life. Judgments about morality cannot be made without
taking into consideration whether or not the deliberate choice of a specific
kind of behaviour is in conformity with the dignity and integral vocation of
the human person. Every choice always implies a reference by the deliberate
will to the goods and evils indicated by the natural law as goods to be pursued
and evils to be avoided. In the case of the positive moral precepts, prudence
always has the task of verifying that they apply in a specific situation, for
example, in view of other duties which may be more important or urgent. But the
negative moral precepts, those prohibiting certain concrete actions or kinds of
behaviour as intrinsically evil, do not allow for any legitimate exception.
They do not leave room, in any morally acceptable way, for the
"creativity" of any contrary determination whatsoever. Once the moral
species of an action prohibited by a universal rule is concretely recognized,
the only morally good act is that of obeying the moral law and of refraining
from the action which it forbids.
68.
Here an important pastoral consideration must be added. According to the logic
of the positions mentioned above, an individual could, by virtue of a
fundamental option, remain faithful to God independently of whether or not
certain of his choices and his acts are in conformity with specific moral norms
or rules. By virtue of a primordial option for charity, that individual could
continue to be morally good, persevere in God's grace and attain salvation,
even if certain of his specific kinds of behaviour were deliberately and
gravely contrary to God's commandments as set forth by the Church.
In point of fact, man does
not suffer perdition only by being unfaithful to that fundamental option
whereby he has made "a free self-commitment to God".113 With
every freely committed mortal sin, he offends God as the giver of the law and
as a result becomes guilty with regard to the entire law (cf
Jas 2:8-11); even if he perseveres
in faith, he loses "sanctifying grace", "charity" and
"eternal happiness".114 As the Council of Trent teaches,
"the grace of justification once received is lost not only by apostasy, by
which faith itself is lost, but also by any other mortal sin".115
Mortal and venial sin
69.
As we have just seen, reflection on the fundamental option has also led some
theologians to undertake a basic revision of the traditional distinction
between mortal sins and venial sins. They insist that the
opposition to God's law which causes the loss of sanctifying grace — and
eternal damnation, when one dies in such a state of sin — could only be the
result of an act which engages the person in his totality: in other words, an
act of fundamental option. According to these theologians, mortal sin, which
separates man from God, only exists in the rejection of God, carried out at a
level of freedom which is neither to be identified with an act of choice nor
capable of becoming the object of conscious awareness. Consequently, they go on
to say, it is difficult, at least psychologically, to accept the fact that a
Christian, who wishes to remain united to Jesus Christ and to his Church, could
so easily and repeatedly commit mortal sins, as the "matter" itself
of his actions would sometimes indicate. Likewise, it would be hard to accept
that man is able, in a brief lapse of time, to sever radically the bond of
communion with God and afterwards be converted to him by sincere repentance.
The gravity of sin, they maintain, ought to be measured by the degree of
engagement of the freedom of the person performing an act, rather than by the
matter of that act.
70.
The Post-Synodal Apostolic Exhortation Reconciliatio et Paenitentia
reaffirmed the importance and permanent validity of the distinction between
mortal and venial sins, in accordance with the Church's tradition. And the 1983
Synod of Bishops, from which that Exhortation emerged, "not only
reaffirmed the teaching of the Council of Trent concerning the existence and
nature of mortal and venial sins, but it also recalled that mortal sin is sin
whose object is grave matter and which is also committed with full knowledge
and deliberate consent".116
The statement of the
Council of Trent does not only consider the "grave matter" of mortal
sin; it also recalls that its necessary condition is "full awareness and
deliberate consent". In any event, both in moral theology and in pastoral
practice one is familiar with cases in which an act which is grave by reason of
its matter does not constitute a mortal sin because of a lack of full awareness
or deliberate consent on the part of the person performing it. Even so,
"care will have to be taken not to reduce mortal sin to an act of 'fundamental
option' — as is commonly said today — against God", seen either as an
explicit and formal rejection of God and neighbour or as an implicit and
unconscious rejection of love. "For mortal sin exists also when a person
knowingly and willingly, for whatever reason, chooses something gravely
disordered. In fact, such a choice already includes contempt for the divine
law, a rejection of God's love for humanity and the whole of creation: the
person turns away from God and loses charity. Consequently, the fundamental
orientation can be radically changed by particular acts. Clearly,
situations can occur which are very complex and obscure from a psychological
viewpoint, and which influence the sinner's subjective imputability.
But from a consideration of the psychological sphere one cannot proceed to
create a theological category, which is precisely what the 'fundamental option'
is, understanding it in such a way that it objectively changes or casts doubt
upon the traditional concept of mortal sin".117
The separation of
fundamental option from deliberate choices of particular kinds of behaviour,
disordered in themselves or in their circumstances, which would not engage that
option, thus involves a denial of Catholic doctrine on mortal sin: "With
the whole tradition of the Church, we call mortal sin the act by which man freely
and consciously rejects God, his law, the covenant of love that God offers,
preferring to turn in on himself or to some created and finite reality,
something contrary to the divine will (conversio
ad creaturam). This can occur in a direct and
formal way, in the sins of idolatry, apostasy and atheism; or in an equivalent
way, as in every act of disobedience to God's commandments in a grave
matter".118
|