The highest rank among fundamental religious truths belongs to the
truth of the existence of God. Objections against the necessity and usefulness
of rationalistic proofs for the benefit of religious truths fall into three
categories: In the first place, these proofs are regarded as impossible.
Secondly, even if possible, they are unnecessary and superfluous. Thirdly, they
are not so much useful as they are harmful.
The opinion that
theoretical and strictly scientific proofs of the existence of God and of other
fundamental religious truths were impossible was expressed for the first time
with complete critical argumentation by the German philosopher, Immanuel Kant,
in his work, Critique of Pure Reason.
However, the followers of positivism were especially energetic in emphasizing
the indemonstrability of religious truth. At times in this denial of the
possibility of the proof of the existence of God, there has appeared either an
incorrect understanding about God or an incorrect understanding about the proof
itself.
For example,
according to Kant’s definition, God is the personified mental ideal of all the
possible perfections. In other words, Kant has no conception of the living
personality of God, but only has a notion of “a godly idea.” Such a subjective
and abstract idea of God does make impossible the proof of God’s objectively
perceptible existence. But this impossibility immediately fades as soon as we
replace the conception of an abstract “idea of God” with a concrete conception
of God as an active, perceptible Being.
Into the basis
of the denial of the possibility of proof of the existence of God there is sometimes
mixed an incomplete understanding of the substance of the proof itself. For
instance, some investigators have defined proof as a conclusion from the higher
to the lower; and, as there is nothing higher than God, the proof of the
existence of God is therefore impossible. But that is an incorrect definition
of the proof. The proof of the existence of God is necessary not for God
Himself, but only for us who are by nature lower than God, and hence struggle
to have faith in God’s existence. The meaning of proofs of
the existence of God are sometimes denied validity on the grounds that
they do not have the character of mathematical precision. But mathematically
exact proofs are very few. In place of them, in philosophy, in science, and in
practical life, other forms of proofs are often used. Even in mathematics there
exist so-called postulates, that is, self-evident truths, which are impossible
to prove exactly, mathematically, and, as a result, they can be doubted. For
instance, the uncertainty inherent in the fifth postulate of Euclid (that is,
that through one point you can draw only one straight line parallel to the
given straight line) led the highly gifted Russian mathematician Lobachevsky to the discovery of a new pan-geometry.
So we see that
even the most exact and conclusive science, mathematics, is based on axioms and
postulates, which, just like all so-called self-evident truths, cannot be
proved and which are accepted on faith. St. Basil the Great is profoundly
correct when he states that in science “faith precedes knowledge.” Everything
that is most basic and elementary in scientific knowledge is unprovable and is accepted on an act of faith. The sciences
usually pride themselves on their exactness and conclusiveness. But is should
not be forgotten that, in the first place, science is composed not only of
facts and “empirical data” (which do not yet give us scientific knowledge), but
also of speculative structures of the mind. These speculative structures can be
argued about, because it is impossible to construct them without elements of
philosophical theory. Secondly, besides exactness of knowledge, one must
discern also its value and meaning. The knowledge of the chemical composition
of stone and the significance of the life of the world and man, as we have
already noted above, have for me a different value than they do for one who
does not believe in God. If exact sciences cannot exactly mathematically prove
basic religious truths, and, in general, cannot answer the most urgent
questions of man’s spirit (for example, the aim and meaning of life), then this
shows only the limits of the scientific method of knowledge, and, therefore,
the boundaries of the meaning of empirical science for man.
Where knowledge
is helpless, faith is lawful. Faith in something which cannot be proved, but at
the same time cannot be disproved by means of scientific knowledge, is
perfectly lawful.
The absence of
the possibility of exact mathematical proof of religious truths, which reveals
the lawful possibility of faith, makes religious truths (and, first of all, the
most important of them — the truth of the existence of God) a subject of the
free will of man. God could prove His existence by a direct appearance in His
power and glory, but He does not desire to force the free will of man and
awaits a free desire, a free faith in Him and toward Him. Again we must conclude
that nothing hinders man’s coming to God by an act of faith, if man desires to
come to Him.
From the
Christian point of view, the impossibility of a scientific, mathematically
exact proof of the existence of God and other religious truths is part of the
nature of things and was originated by God Himself. In science and philosophy
there are different methods of proofs or, rather, persuasive considerations, perhaps
not so persuasive in a mathematical sense, but nonetheless speaking strongly in
favor of one or another theory or hypothesis. The same is true with religion.
The opinion is
often expressed that, after Kant’s critique of the methods of proving the truth
of God’s existence, this impossible task should not be approached anymore. This
may be answered as follows. In the first place, Kant himself, after a critique
of the existing proofs, tried to found a new form of so-called ethical proof.
The history of philosophy contains other significant instances where a highly
gifted philosopher began to defend anew ideas already examined and abandoned
earlier. For instance, the ontological proof of the existence of God, first expressed
by Anselm of Canterbury, has at times stimulated a renewed interest toward it
and new argumentation in its defense. Such attempts were made by Descartes and Leibnitz before Kant, and by Hegel after Kant.
Kant’s critique
itself involved not so much a loss of interest, as, instead, a heightening of
interest in proofs of God’s existence. Famous and weighty is
the criticism of Kant and the refutation of his ideas in works such as those by
Ulrich, God and Nature and God and Man, and in the course by
Professor N.P. Rozhdestvensky, Christian Apologetics, and others.
Speaking
practically, Kant’s critique does not refute the proof of the existence of God,
but simply points out that these proofs do not have the mathematically exact
character of scientific proofs.
In regard to the
conclusiveness of proofs in general, one should remember the remarks of Pascal
(Thoughts on Religion), that if
geometry could provoke man’s passions, people would be found who would begin to
object against the most evident geometrical statements. Contradictions and
objections against the most clear and convincing proofs are very often met in
practical life where man’s passions are touched upon. In political, religious,
philosophical and even in scientific controversy, we often meet with this
phenomenon. Very often exceptionally convincing proofs, which do not convince
an obstinate opponent, do convince a listening bystander present at the argument
who is objectively weighing the arguments of the opponents.
Sometimes you
can hear objections against proofs of the existence of God in this form: Proofs
are not necessary for the faithful, and an atheist will not be convinced
anyhow. In answer to this it must be said that if we have before us an atheist
whose convictions are founded on an unwillingness to believe in God, then such an
atheist cannot be convinced. If, however, we have before us an atheist who,
through a misunderstanding due to insufficient education, regards his atheism as scientifically proved,
then such a one can be convinced.
Also, not every
believing person is disinterested in the rationalistic proofs of the religious
truths in which he believes. A striking example is the prayer with which the
profoundly believing scholar and philosopher, the Bishop Anselm of Canterbury,
preceded his so-called ontological proof of the truth of the existence of God:
“Lord! You grant wisdom to faith; give me also the wisdom to perceive that You exist, as I believe, and that You are the same being as
my faith describes You to me.” Love not only contemplates but also wants to
know its object. The lover of God lawfully wants to perceive him with all the
powers of his spirit — the powers given us by God Himself. Numbered among these
powers, granted to us by God, is also the honest intellect.
Some
investigators regard the absence of one fundamental and convincing proof of the
existence of God and the replacing of that one by several proofs as proving the
weakness of the latter. This profoundly incorrect! As the steeple of a building
is not founded on the foundation alone, but on the many parts of the building
simultaneously, so also the proof of the truth of God’s existence is founded on
the combination of several separate and particular proofs.
The Holy
Scripture rarely mentions the so-called proof of God’s existence, regarding
this basic religious truth to be so evident that one who denies it is qualified
as senseless. The fool hath said in his
heart: There is no God (Psalm 13:1). It is regrettable that the authority
of the Holy Scripture has its full meaning for the faithful, but for skeptics
it has no meaning whatsoever.
After these
preliminary remarks, we will now proceed to an examination of the specific
so-called proofs of the existence of God.
1. Cosmological
proof of the existence of God is one of the most ancient. Holy Scripture often
points to a creature as a manifest testimony of the existence of the Creator of
the world: The heavens declare the glory
of God, and the firmament proclaimeth the work of His
hands (Psalm 18). For the invisible
things of Him from the creation of the world are clearly seen, being understood
by the things that are made, even his eternal power and Godhead (Romans 1:20).
Among the Holy
Fathers of the Church, cosmological proof of God’s existence is presented by
St. Athanasius the Great in the form of a conclusion
from the fact of the existence of creation to the fact of the existence of the
Creator; by St. Basil the Great and St. Gregory the Theologian, by means of
refuting the opinion of the accidental origin and preservation of world laws;
by St. John of Damascus, in the form of a conclusion from the changeable to the
unchangeable. In the history of philosophy, the oldest assertions in the
defense of cosmological proof are met in Aristotle (as a conclusion from motion
noticed in the world to the existence of a Prime-mover). Leibnitz
forms this proof by a conclusion, not from motion to a Prime-mover, but from
the conditional to the absolute. The philosopher, Wolf, makes it a conclusion
from the accidental to the indispensable.
Cosmological
proof usually rests on two laws of logic: the law of causality and the law of
sufficient reason. The first demands the recognition of the original cause of
the world, and the second affirms that nothing but the highest universal Cause
can be recognized on a sufficient basis as the true original cause of the
world.
Everything in
the world has its cause. Every cause in its turn is the consequence of another
cause. This means that everything in the world has the cause of its existence
outside of itself; nothing is original (self-existing). Therefore, the world,
too, in totality, is not self-existing and must have a cause for its existence,
and this cause must be outside of this world. Such a cause can be only a
universally all-highest Being: God.
This was the
object of the criticism of Kant and many other philosophers. The main objection
to this proof was that we do not have enough reason to search for the origin of
world phenomena in another, super-sensual world since it is possible that the
law of causality is valid only as to this world’s phenomena. Also, in Kant’s
opinion, there is not a sufficient basis to deny the possibility of
self-existing world phenomena.
Contemporary
physics, in the persons of the scholars Planck and Jeans, categorically denies
the possibility of self-existing world phenomena, and, by doing so, again
vindicates cosmological proof to a sufficient degree. As to the question of
causality, if there is no absolute necessity to recognize its action in a super-sensual
world, then there is also no absolute necessity to deny it there.
2. The Beginning.
If we do exist,
there are only two possible explanations as to how our existence came to be.
Either we had a beginning or we did not have a beginning. The Bible says, “In
the beginning God created the heaven
and the earth” (Genesis 1 :1). The atheist has always
maintained that there was no beginning. The idea is that matter has always
existed in the form of either matter or energy; and all that has happened is
that matter has been changed from form to form, but it has always been. The Humanist Manifesto says, “Matter is self-existing and not created,” and that is a concise
statement of the atheist's belief.
The way we
decide whether the atheist is correct or not is to see what science has discovered
about this question. The picture below on the left represents our part of the
cosmos. Each of the disk shaped objects is a galaxy like our Milky Way. All of
these galaxies are moving relative to each other. Their movement has a very
distinct pattern which causes the distance between the galaxies to increase
with every passing day. If we had three galaxies located at positions A, B. and
C in the second diagram below, and if they are located as shown, tomorrow they
will be further apart. The triangle they form will be bigger. The day after
tomorrow the triangle will be bigger yet. We live in an expanding universe that
gets bigger and bigger and bigger with every passing day.
Now let us suppose that we made time run backwards! If we are
located at a certain distance today, then yesterday we were closer together.
The day before that, we were still closer. Ultimately, where must all the
galaxies have been? At a point! At the beginning! At what scientists call a
singularity! A second proof is seen in the energy sources that fuel the cosmos.
The picture to the right is a picture of the sun. Like all stars, the sun
generates its energy by a nuclear process known as thermonuclear fusion. Every
second that passes, the sun compresses 564 million tons of hydrogen into 560
million tons of helium with 4 million tons of matter released as energy. In
spite of that tremendous consumption of fuel, the sun has only used up 2% of
the hydrogen it had the day it came into existence. The process fueling this
incredible furnace is not used by our sun alone. Every star in the sky
generates its energy in the same way. Throughout the cosmos there are 25
quintillion stars, each converting hydrogen into
helium, thereby reducing the total amount of hydrogen in the cosmos. Just think
about it! If everywhere in the cosmos hydrogen is being consumed and if the
process has been going on forever, how much hydrogen should be left?
Suppose one attempts
to drive an automobile without putting any more gas (fuel) into it. As he
drives and drives, what is eventually going to happen? He is
am going to run out of gas. If the cosmos has been here forever, we
would have run out of hydrogen long ago! The fact is, however, that the sun
still has 98% of its original hydrogen. The fact is that hydrogen is the most
abundant material in the universe! Everywhere we look in space we can see the
hydrogen 21 cm line in the spectrum — a piece of light only given off by
hydrogen. This could not be unless we had a beginning!
A third scientific
proof that the atheist is wrong is seen in the second law of thermodynamics. In
any closed system, things tend to become disordered. If an automobile is driven
for years and years without repair, for example, it will become so disordered
that it would not run any more. Getting old is simple conformity to the second
law of thermodynamics. In space, things also get old. Astronomers refer to the
aging process as heat death. If the cosmos is “everything that ever was or is
or ever will be,” as Dr. Carl Sagan is so fond of
saying, nothing could be added to it to improve its order or repair it. Even a
universe that expands and collapses and expands again forever would die because
it would lose light and heat each time it expanded and rebounded.
The atheist's
assertion that matter/energy is eternal is scientifically wrong. The biblical
assertion that there was a beginning is scientifically correct.
3. The Cause.
If we know the
creation has a beginning, we are faced with another logical question: was the
creation caused or was it not caused? The Bible states, “In the beginning God created the heaven and the earth.” Not only does the Bible maintain that
there was a cause — a creation — but it also tells us what the cause was. It
was God. The atheist tells us that “matter is self-existing and not created.”
If matter had a beginning and yet was uncaused, one must logically maintain
that something would have had to come into existence out of nothing. From empty
space with no force, no matter, no energy, and no intelligence, matter would
have to become existent. Even if this could happen by some strange new process
unknown to science today, there is a logical problem.
In order for
matter to come out of nothing, all of our scientific laws dealing with the conservation
of matter/energy would have to be wrong, invalidating all of chemistry. All of
our laws of conservation of angular momentum would have to be wrong,
invalidating all of physics. All of our laws of conservation of electric charge
would have to be wrong, invalidating all electronics and demanding that your TV
set not work! Your television set may not work, but that is not the reason! In
order to believe matter is uncaused, one has to discard known laws and
principles of science. No reasonable person is going to do this simply to
maintain a personal atheistic position.
The atheist's
assertion that matter is eternal is wrong. The atheist's assertion that the universe
is uncaused and self existing is also incorrect The Bible's assertion that
there was a beginning which was caused is supported strongly by the available
scientific evidence.
4. The Design.
If we know that
the creation had a beginning and we know that the beginning was caused, there
is one last question for us to answer — what was the cause? The Bible tells us
that God was the cause. We are further told that the God who did the causing
did so with planning and reason and logic. Romans 1:20
tells us that we can know God exists “through the things he has made.” The
atheist, on the other hand, will try to convince us that we are the product of
chance. Julian Huxley once said: We are as much a product of blind forces as is
the falling of a stone to earth or the ebb and flow of the tides. We have just
happened, and man was made flesh by a long series of singularly beneficial
accidents.
The subject of
design has been one that has been explored in many different ways. For most of
us, simply looking at our newborn child is enough to rule out chance.
Modern-day scientists like Paul Davies and Frederick Hoyle and others are
raising elaborate objections to the use of chance in explaining natural
phenomena. A principle of modern science has emerged in the 1980s called “the anthropic principle.” The basic thrust of the anthropic principle is that chance is simply not a valid mechanism to explain the atom or life.
If chance is not valid, we are constrained to reject Huxley's claim and to
realize that we are the product of an intelligent God.
Some investigators point out that
cosmological proof does not demonstrate a personal God. This is correct.
Cosmological proof makes no pretence to this. It affirms only that there is a
sufficient basis for the recognition of a super-universal, higher creative
force, on which the origin of the universe depends, and that this force has a
real existence.
The teleological proof of the existence of God, based on the
expedient arrangement of the world, results necessarily in affirming the
existence of an Intellectual Being, the cause of this expedience. If cosmological proof concentrates on the investigation of the
original cause of the universe, then the teleological proof interests itself
chiefly in the final purpose. It examines the world not only as something
existing and needing an explanation of its emergence, but as something whole,
harmonious, artistic, proportionate, expedient; pointing to the wisdom of the
Author of this expedience.
Cosmological
proof demands recognition of God as a very wise, mighty, creative force,
capable of creating the world; the teleological proof demands the recognition
of God as an Intellectual Personality, capable of high purpose and good order
in the created world. Both proofs complement each other. Teleological proof is
not greater than the cosmological and has need for it. For, as Kant so justly
pointed out, the teleological proof does not prove the Creator of the world,
but the Creator of a well-ordered expedience in the world which could have
existed along with God eternally in the form of inert, formless matter.
A world-view is
possible in which God and matter co-exist eternally, and in which God
transformed this co-eternal matter into an expedient world. God is understood,
in this case, as the Demiurge, that is, the expert arranger of the world, and
not the Creator of the world from nothing. But Christianity categorically
asserts that God created the world from nothing. The existence of matter
co-eternal with God is impossible, since, in such a case, God would not be the
Absolute. It is of note that contemporary physical science (Plank, Jeans, and
others) also affirms that matter cannot be eternal.
Cosmological and
teleological proofs are closely related. Only in their synthesis can be
inferred the proof of God as an Absolute Personality. In ancient philosophy,
many philosophers (for example, Socrates, Plato, and, before them, also,
Anaxagoras) recognized the teleological proof as one of the strongest and most
conclusive arguments in defense of the existence of a Higher
intellect. In general, however, the teleological proof is regarded as chiefly
biblical, as the Holy Scripture often refers to the expedient ordainment of the
world as graphic proof of the wisdom of the Creator. For instance, in the
Psalms of David we find much contemplation of the beauties of the world, with
inference from this of godly wisdom.
Teleological
proof can be divided into two main aspects: 1) the so-called physico-teleological, inferring from the expedience and
planned system of the external world to a wise Author of it, and 2) historico-teleological, inferring from the intellectual
course of the historical life of man to a wise Ruler of the fates of man. The
Orthodox Church sometimes calls God “Master of Life.”
Objections
against teleological proof usually take one of three main directions: 1) the denial
of the expedient ordering of nature; 2) the explanation of expedience as
accidental; 3) the denial of the consciousness and personality of the cause of
the expedience of the world.
As to the first
point, the criticism comes to pointing out several popular phenomena of the
world which do not appear to have expedience. The answer to this is that we
sometimes do not know, do not understand, and do not see the purpose and sense
of some particular phenomena, but this does not mean that, in general, these
phenomena have no purpose and sense. With this, the general experience of
nature can by no means be denied. Exceptions are extraordinarily insignificant
and can be simply unexplained expediencies from the point of view of a higher
plan unapproachable to us and with purposes incomprehensible to us.
The explanation
of expediency as ordinary chance does not withstand strict criticism. If the
expedience of a machine (for example, a steam machine) cannot be explained as
accidental and demands the recognition of the presence of consciousness which
crafted this expedient machine, then it is that much more difficult to explain
the expediency of consciousness itself, and, finally, the expediency of the
entire universe, as accidental.
If we conjecture
that this question is unsolvable by exact knowledge and is subject only to
faith, then faith in a causative expediency certainly has many more sufficient
reasons than a naïve and contradictory faith in causeless expedience. In
short, plan, aim and sense (which can be disclosed by analyzing expedient
phenomena of the world) should be regarded by normal consciousness as primary,
preliminary phenomena and not as secondary or subsequent.
The last
objection, denying the reasonableness and personality of God and explaining the
cause of expediency as blind unconscious will, also cannot stand serious
criticism. Some critics point to animal instinct as an example of expedient
action. They say, “The instinctive activity of animals is originated without
reason.” This is not correct. An animal acts without being conscious of the aim
of its action, but not without aim. An animal acts in conformity with an aim
unrecognizable to itself.
From this, it
follows that the causes of the expedient actions of animals and nature, in
general, are not animals and nature themselves; but it does not follow that
there is no Creator consciously assigning the aims, which are unconsciously
accomplished in an unconscious nature. Observing the expedient arrangement of
the world, we affirm a conscious Author of the world — i.e. one with an
intellect, to whom came the idea of an expedient
arrangement of the world, and also one with power, which accomplished this idea
in a substantial existence of the world. Only to a reasonable, conscious,
personal Being can an expedient creation be obliged for its origin.
Historico-teleological proof of the
existence of an Intellect-God is more debatable. This proof, leading to an
understanding of the profound significance of man’s history, is accessible to
few people (the philosophical theory of reality). For those to whom it is
accessible, this proof is exceptionally convincing.
Ontological and
ethical proofs of God’s existence are called inner proofs in that they are
taken from our inner experience, as distinguished from external cosmological
and teleological proofs which are taken from external experience.
The meaning of
inner proofs is very important, for without them, external proofs would not
have force. If we had not the former, there would not be so much strength
expended on the latter. If in our consciousness there were not an idea of God
and an inner conviction of His reality, together with the immense practical
importance of the ethical meaning of this conviction, we would not have the
impetus to search for careful proofs of the existence of God in external experience.
Ontological
proof of the existence of God was formulated first in the 11th
century by the western theological scholar Archbishop Anselm of Canterbury. The
author of this proof regards it not as a fruit of his own mind, but as received
with the help of a higher inspiration.
The basic
thought of this proof is that in the inherent idea of a higher, all-perfect and
endless Being, there is of necessity also included the idea of the reality of
this Being, because the All-Perfect cannot be unreal!
Critics,
especially Kant, consider it incompetent to conclude that God exists based on
human thoughts of Him. To make such a conclusion is impossible, says Kant,
because we can have (and do have) dreamy ideas which do not conform to the
existence of actual objects.
Long before
Kant, this objection was foreseen by the learned French philosopher and
mathematician Descartes. Analyzing chimerical, conditionally and
unconditionally necessary ideas, Descartes came to the conclusion that
unconditional necessity truly belongs to the idea of an all-perfect Being. Ontological proof was also defended by Leibniz and
Hegel. The latter, taking exception to Kant, cited the
following considerations. Ontological proof does not at all assert that all
ideas must necessarily assume the existence of the thing corresponding to the
idea. It does not conclude the existence of the All-Perfect from understanding
it, but insists that in understanding the All-Perfect, there is already contained
an understanding of its existence. We can no more think of an all-perfect Being
as not existing, than we can think of a triangle as not being a triangle.
Therefore, the
ontological proof can be finally formulated thus: because in the soul of man there
exists an idea of a Being, which with a fullness of
perfections is united also to a real existence, it necessarily follows that
this being must exist, not only in mind, but in actual fact.
Ethical proof of
God’s existence can be of a practical or theoretical character. Practical,
ethical proof results in pointing to the fact that faith in God assists
improvement of morality, while faith in atheism usually leads to a fall in
morality.
Attempts to
prove that atheism, on the contrary, assists in bettering morals are absurd and
are not corroborated by actual experience. Many defenders of atheism,
recognizing the beneficence of religion for morality, expressed the thought
that this does not at all prove the truth of religion. However, it is very
strange that in such a case a paradoxical situation exists — a false conviction
(faith in God) leads to a betterment of morality, while a true conviction
(faith in atheism) assists in corrupting morals. Instead of quibbling, ought
not the truth of religion and the falsity of atheism
be accepted, since the former assists the betterment of morality and the
latter, on the contrary, ruins it?
The indication that atheists exist who do live morally does not
refute the general conclusion about the ethical benefits of religion. The truth
is that many people do not follow their theoretical convictions in practical
life. This contradiction between theory and practice leads to the result that
some who theoretically espouse atheism in their practical life follow the laws
of Christian morals. But wherever a complete accord exists between theory and
practical action, where there is no dissension and contradiction between theory
and practice, based on this theory, there cannot even be talk of the ethical
good conduct of an atheist.
At times,
atheists indicate that believers live in perpetual fear before the Almighty
Sovereign God for their misdemeanors, while the atheist, free of religious
convictions, does not experience this fear. This can be answered in the following
manner.
The fear of
moral responsibility before God is an exceptionally beneficent fear. This fear
appears in a man not when he lives a moral life, but only when he performs
unethical actions, transgressing moral law, given to us from God, according to the
conviction of believers. On the other hand, does not the atheist also have
fear? If life has no meaning and aim, and every occurrence depends on a simple
accident of an indifferent, cruel nature, does not a man acquire fear before
these inexorably cruel happenings upon which all life wholly depends? And,
conversely, does not the conviction of a religious man assist in reassuring him
that Almighty God Himself, Who is understood as love and higher justice, guards
a man and leads him to eternal blessings?
Theoretical and
so-called scientifically philosophic methods of ethical proof of God’s existence
come in two main forms. Before Kant, in both theology and philosophy, ethical
proof of God’s existence was deduced from the ethical law contained in
conscience, to the existence of God as the Creator and Legislator of this law.
Kant gave to the ethical proof a different basis. For harmony between virtue
and blessedness, which is demanded by our ethical conscience, it is necessary
to recognize God, because this harmony can be accomplished and fully realized
only by God Himself. In both its forms (pre-Kant and Kant), ethical proof has
its force. These forms not only do not exclude, but, on the contrary,
complement each other.
Careful analysis
of the ethical conscience of man shows us that having freedom of action, man,
after performing immoral actions, experiences pangs of conscience, and, on the
other hand, after fulfillment of the demands of ethical law, he experiences a
spiritual satisfaction in being aware of a fulfilled debt. In other words, the
freedom of man’s will is guarded from arbitrariness by the presence of a higher
ethical law which approves or censures its actions. Man, having free will,
nonetheless feels this law above himself as an unconditional, commanding force.
Consequently, it could not have been man himself who created this law and
placed it above himself.
Ethical law also
cannot be deduced from any other side of man’s nature. However, if ethical law
is not created by man and cannot be deduced from anything conditional and
accidental but is deposited in man’s spirit as an unconditional higher
requirement, then its origin can be explained only by its being deposited by a
higher, unconditional Being, God, and presents in itself nothing other than the
voice of God in man’s soul and the inner revelation of the holy and
unconditional will of God in man’s spirit.
Concerning
Kant’s basis for ethical law, it is formulated by the author himself in such a
way: “We are aware of the ethical law within ourselves demanding our
fulfillment of a debt without any search for gain, benefit or pleasure;
besides, we are conscious within ourselves of a need to attain the higher
welfare. Even though in our ethical deeds we should not be governed by
self-interested ideas of rewards, we have in our spirit a permanent demand that
virtue should have a worthy reward and vice a worthy punishment. This is the
law of truth. The requirement that virtue would be rewarded by a corresponding
measure of fortune is so deeply placed in our spirit that we can in no way
erase it within ourselves. The union of the purest morals with perfect fortune
or blessedness, therefore, constitutes the highest blessing to which the spirit
of man aspires by virtue of its own ethical nature. But the union of fortune
and virtue in a completely equal measure does not depend on us ourselves. The
organization of our morality depends on our freedom, but fortune does not
depend on our authority. And experience shows that virtue in the present life
more often is not rewarded by deserved fortune. Meanwhile, our ethical
conscience urgently demands that virtue should be inseparable from fortune, and
from this alliance of virtue and fortune, supreme welfare would result. If it
is not in man’s power to establish an alliance between virtue and fortune, then
there must be another ethically good Being who wants to and can effect this;
that is, to reward virtue with fortune worthy of it. Such a Being, therefore,
is the one God.”
Kant also
expressed his proof in this fashion: “Nature cannot establish compliance between
virtue and fortune. This impels us to recognize the existence of a cause
differing from nature and not depending on it. This cause must possess not only
force and might, but also intellect; it must be such a force which, in might
and will and mind, is higher than nature. And such a Being is God only. He
wants to and can also sanction an alliance between ethics and virtue.”
From his proofs,
Kant deduces God’s perfections. “As one who desires the highest good, God
Himself must be the highest Good, filled with holiness. As one capable of
combining virtue and fortune, He must be All-Mighty, All-Knowing, All-Wise,
etc., and, in every case, a particular Being.”
The deficiency
in Kant’s argumentation is found in that he separates the understanding of
virtue from the understanding of fortune (or blessedness), and, therefore, he
understands a compensating reward as something eternal, when, according to
Christian morals, true virtue finds its reward in itself and does not require
any external repayment. Even in pre-Christian philosophy we find such an
understanding of good. “Virtue is fortune,” says Socrates. Hegel, in his
criticism of Kant’s ethical proof, with complete justice, notes that “virtue in
consequence of its expedient activity directly brings with it self-enjoyment
and self-satisfaction.”
The Savior
Himself said in regard to virtue, which cannot be put into life without moral
effort and grace sent from above (and consequently, being a sort of yoke
limiting man’s freedom) the following clear and simple words of Truth: Take My yoke upon you, and learn of Me; for
I am meek and lowly in heart; and ye shall find rest unto your souls. For My yoke is easy, and My burden is light (Matt. 11:29-30). The yoke of Christ is goodness;
that is, Christian value is already in itself a blessing.
Combining all aspects and formulations of
ethical proof of God’s existence, we can arrive at the following generalized
conclusion. The existence of moral law concluding in a demand
for moral good, which already in itself comprises the greatest spiritual good,
and which is impossible to explain or to accomplish without help from above, is
the theoretical proof of the existence of God, receiving its fullest
justification during its practical verification by ethical life according to
the teachings of Christ.
The truth of
God’s existence, finally accepted with the assistance of faith, has exceptionally
convincing and highly rational principles, permitting us to maintain the
irrefutable, local possibility of this truth. The impossibility of refuting
this truth by any local considerations and the impossibility of proving it
exactly and mathematically, methodologically justifies the application to it of
faith as an act of the free will of man.